On the Old Saw. Immanuel Kant

On the Old Saw - Immanuel Kant


Скачать книгу

      

ON THE OLD SAW

      ON THE OLD SAW

      THAT MAY BE RIGHT IN THEORY BUT IT WON’T WORK IN PRACTICE

      IMMANUEL KANT

      Translated by E. B. Ashton Introduction by George Miller

      University of Pennsylvania Press Philadelphia

      This translation is based on the German edition (known as Akademie Ausgabe) by the Koniglich Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, Kant’s Gesammelte Schriften (Berlin and Leipzig: W. de Gruyter, 1923), 8: 273-313. The approximate pagination of that edition is indicated at the foot of each page of the translation.

      English text copyright © 1974 University of Pennsylvania Press

      All rights reserved

      Printed in the United States of America on acid-free paper

      Published by

      University of Pennsylvania Press

      Philadelphia, Pennsylvania 19104-4112

      Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data

      Kant, Immanuel, 1724-1804.

      On the old saw: that may be right in theory but it won’t work in practice / Immanuel Kant; translated by E. B. Ashton ; introduction by George Miller.

      [Über den Gemeinspruch: Das mag in der Theorie richtig sein, taugt aber nicht für die Praxis. English]

      p. cm.

      ISBN-13: 978-0-8122-1058-3

      ISBN-10: 0-8122-1058-1 (pbk.: alk. paper)

      1. Theory (Philosophy). 2. Practice (Philosophy). 3. Ethics. 4. Law—Philosophy. I. Title B2794.U33 E52 1974

      193

      73083291

      In Memoriam

      Fred Wieck

      our now silent collaborator,

      one of the last of the civilized editors

       Contents

       Foreword by John R. Silber

       Introduction by George Miller

       ON THE OLD SAW: THAT MAY BE RIGHT IN THEORY BUT IT WON’T WORK IN PRACTICE

       I. On the Relation of Theory to Practice in Morality in General (in reply to some exceptions taken by Professor Garve)

       II. On the Relation of Theory to Practice in Constitutional Law (contra Hobbes)

       III. On the Relation of Theory to Practice in International Law—A General-Philanthropic, i.e., Cosmopolitan View (contra Mendelssohn)

      Foreword

      Few people are so ignorant that they will dispute the value of theory. Yet men commonly denounce proposals that apply theory in daily life. Many of the finest insights of science, medicine, agriculture, ethics, law, and politics have been summarily rejected with the ritualistic formula: “That may be right in theory, but it wont work in practice.” Fully appreciative of the enervating and pernicious influence of this nostrum, Kant published in 1793 the most rigorous and sustained critique that it or any other cliche has ever received.

      Kant’s essay, addressed to a broad intellectual audience, is one of the most neglected though most important documents of the Enlightenment. It is here published in English as a separate volume for the first time. Its relevance today depends least on its contribution to Kantian studies, though in “Theory and Practice” Kant elaborates significantly on the role of happiness in ethics and provides his clearest discussion of moral feelings and the nature of ethical motivation. Its importance for today derives primarily from Kant’s brilliant discussion of critical political issues that are of intense contemporary interest—the nature of political authority, the right of revolution, freedom of the pen, the authority to make war, and the preservation of peace. Although these issues, raised by Hobbes, Locke and Rousseau, were central to political discussion at the founding of our Republic, their relevance even now is undiminished.

      Kant examines the cliché from two general aspects. First, he discusses the problems involved in applying any theory and the paradoxical fact that there are theoreticians who lack the judgment (mother wit, or common sense) to apply theory effectively. But Kant argues that we cannot reject theory in any field on the basis of inadequate application: the soundness of theory depends upon its applicability, and inapplicability is clear evidence of incomplete theory or poor judgment. Second, Kant shows in terms of specific highly controversial examples that ethical and political theories, when intelligently interpreted and applied, work also in practice.

      In the discussion of political theory, Kant develops a highly plausible contract theory of government. Seeing the social contract not as an historical fact but as a rational statement of the necessary conditions of social organization, Kant argues for limitations on the authority of both the sovereign and the people. Though Kant questions the right of revolution, he recognizes that the people “have inalienable rights against the head of state,” In this regard he argues: “The citizen must be free to inform the public of his views on whatever in the sovereign decrees appears to him as a wrong against the community, and he must be granted this freedom by the sovereign himself.” “Freedom of the pen,” Kant continues, “… is the sole shield of popular rights, for to deny the people this freedom would not merely deprive them of every claim to justice in regard to the supreme commander; … it would also deprive the supreme commander, whose will commands the subjects as citizens only by representing the general will of the people, of any knowledge of matters which he himself would change if only he knew them. Hence, to limit this freedom would bring him into contradiction with himself.”

      Kant, as shown by this example, thus offers a strong rational case for liberalism that is untouched by the rhetoric of contemporary radical and conservative criticism.

      In the discussion of international law, Kant presents the rational, moral demand for world federation. Kant recognizes man’s fascination with war: “Nowhere does human nature appear less lovable than in the relations of whole nations to each other. No state’s independence or possessions are even for a moment safe from the others. The will to subjugate another, or encroach upon what belongs to him, is always present.” And he argues that the “only possible remedy is international law based on public statutes backed by power.” Kant’s hope for world peace does not rest on an optimistic view of human nature but on his belief that “the distress of ceaseless warfare must compel men to adopt a … federation under jointly agreed international law.” Laws and institutions are, according to Kant, essential if ethical and political theory are to work in practice. The preservation of peace will depend upon placing the decision to make war in the hands of the people. Kant writes: “Impotence must finally accomplish what good will ought to have done but did not: the organization of every state’s internal affairs so that the decisive voice on whether or not to wage war is not that of the head of state—whom the war costs actually nothing—but that of the people, who pay for it.”

      Throughout this essay Kant exhibits his remarkable rational clarity and principled optimism along with his determined empiricism and historical doubts. “I put my trust in theory. At the same time, I trust in the nature of things, and also take account of human nature which I cannot, or will not, consider so steeped in evil that in the end reason should not triumph …” This is the hope or enlightenment of


Скачать книгу