Overcoming Challenges in the Mental Capacity Act 2005. Camillia Kong

Overcoming Challenges in the Mental Capacity Act 2005 - Camillia Kong


Скачать книгу
defining capacity, requiring capacity to be assessed in relation to each particular decision at the time the decision needs to be made, and not the person’s ability to make decisions generally. Further, the inability to make the particular decision in question must be because of ‘an impairment of, or a disturbance in the functioning of, the mind or brain.’ Precisely how we are to interpret the words ‘because of’ is addressed in greater detail below.

      Section 4, in turn, sets out a checklist of factors that must be considered in deciding what is in a person’s best interests, aimed at identifying those issues most relevant to the individual who lacks capacity (as opposed to the decision-maker or any other persons). Although the test is intended to be an objective one, the courts have made clear that the purpose of the best interests is to require the decision-maker to consider matters from the person’s point of view (Aintree University Hospitals NHS Foundation Trust v James [2013] UKSC 67). The person’s ascertainable wishes and feelings therefore carry great weight, even if they are not determinative (Briggs v Briggs & Ors [2016] EWCOP 53).

      Standing alongside the MCA is the inherent jurisdiction of the High Court to protect ‘vulnerable adults’: those who have mental capacity applying the MCA test, but who are or are reasonably believed to be, either (1) under constraint or (2) subject to coercion or undue influence or (3) for some other reason deprived of the capacity to make the relevant decision, or disabled from making a free choice, or incapacitated or disabled from giving or expressing a real and genuine consent (A Local Authority v (1) MA (2) NA and (3) SA [2005] EWHC 2942; endorsed in DL v A Local Authority and Others [2012] EWCA Civ 253). The precise extent of the High Court’s jurisdiction – described in DL v A Local Authority and Others as ‘the great safety net’ – is unclear. In particular, it is ambiguous as to whether it is limited to taking steps directed against those who are coercing or placing the individual under duress, or whether the High Court can take steps directed against the vulnerable adult herself (i.e., to remove her from the place where she is subject to coercion).

      As discussed in Chapter 6, we take the view that, while there is undoubtedly an important place for the use of the inherent jurisdiction to create a ‘safe space’ around the individual, its use against the person herself is difficult to reconcile with the distinction currently drawn in the law between those with capacity and those without capacity. There are other ways in which to draw the line, but for better or worse, the law at present in England and Wales does draw this distinction. One of the key purposes of this book is to outline how we can better respond within the framework of the MCA to those situations in which a person is suffering harm as a result of a combination of a cognitive impairment and the actions of those around them. We address this in the second section of this chapter after we have sketched an outline of how the CRPD challenges both law and practice in this area.

      • We do not consider the concept of mental capacity to be fundamentally illegitimate, even if we would be the first to admit that how it is assessed often leaves much to be desired.

      • We do not consider the concept of ‘best interests’ to be fundamentally illegitimate, especially where it is interpreted in the fashion required by the case law, which requires real weight to be given to the wishes and feelings of the individual.

      • As discussed further in Chapter 2, we consider that the approach of the Committee on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities is predicated on an extremely ‘thin’ version of autonomy which does not always serve the interests of individuals with cognitive impairments.

      • While it is not the primary focus of this book, there may also be circumstances when, so as to secure these same interests, care or treatment may need to be delivered to an individual lacking capacity to consent. Again, such may be done in the face of her objection where there are sufficiently cogent reasons to consider that such will secure her health, welfare, self-respect and dignity.

      Capacity: causative nexus or embedded within actual circumstances?

      As set out above, we share the view that the concept of mental capacity is legitimate; further, we share the aim that we want to write a book which is of use to practitioners applying the MCA as it stands. However, we also share grave reservations about one model of decision-making capacity which entirely divorces the individual’s cognitive abilities from the circumstances in which she finds herself. As we have seen above, the MCA provides that a person lacks capacity in relation to a matter if at the material time, she is unable to make a decision in relation to it (i.e., she cannot understand, retain, use or weigh the relevant information, or communicate her decision) because of a disturbance or impairment


Скачать книгу