River Restoration. Группа авторов

River Restoration - Группа авторов


Скачать книгу
in the process of large‐scale nature‐transforming national projects: focusing on the case of the Four Major Rivers Restoration Project in Korea. Development and Society 43(1): 109–141.

      205 Zhang, Y., Sheng, L., and Luo, Y. (2019). Evaluation of households’ willingness to accept the ecological restoration of rivers flowing in china. Environmental Progress & Sustainable Energy 38(4): 13094.

      206 Zhao, J., Liu, Q., Lin, L., et al. (2013). Assessing the comprehensive restoration of an urban river: an integrated application of contingent valuation in Shanghai, China. Science of the Total Environment 458: 517–526.

      207 Zingraff‐Hamed, A., Noack, M., Greulich, S., et al. (2018). Model‐based evaluation of urban river restoration: conflicts between sensitive fish species and recreational users. Sustainability 10(6): 1747.

      208 Zube, E.H. (1999). Environmental perception. In: Encyclopedia of Earth Science (eds D.E. Alexander and R.W. Fairbridge), 214–216. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Springer.

      209 Zube, E.H., Sell, J.L., and Taylor, J.G. (1982). Landscape perception: research, application and theory. Landscape Planning 9(1): 1–33.

      Notes

      1 1 In this chapter, the adjective “societal” is used to refer to all work addressing the social, political, and economic issues involved in river restoration.

      2 2 According to the IPBES (2020), ecosystem services are “the benefits people obtain from ecosystems. In the Millennium Ecosystem Assessment, ecosystem services can be divided into supporting, regulating, provisioning and cultural. This classification, however, is superseded in IPBES assessments by the system used under ‘nature’s contributions to people’. This is because IPBES recognises that many services fit into more than one of the four categories. For example, food is both a provisioning service and also, emphatically, a cultural service, in many cultures.”

Part II People–River Relationships: From Ethics to Politics

       Henry Dicks

       Faculté de Philosophie, Université Jean Moulin Lyon, Lyon, France

      Restoration ecology is sometimes considered a science (Bradshaw 1993; Palmer et al. 1997). As Higgs (1994, p. 134) notes, this promotes a problematic view of restoration ecology as “austere,” “disengaged,” and thus essentially independent of ethics. Further, even the very briefest examination of the academic literature on the subject shows that ethical considerations are of central importance to restoration ecology. In particular, the literature abounds with radical uncertainties as to the basic goal or goals of restoration. Should we be restoring past ecosystems and, if so, what precise moment in the past should we take as our reference point (Diamond 1987)? Given the essentially dynamic nature of ecosystems and the high likelihood of significant anthropogenic climate change in the near future, would it not make more sense to make restoration “forward‐looking” (Rolston 2000; Hobbs and Harris 2001)? Or should restorations be modeled rather on intact ecosystems of the present that share similar traits to the destroyed or degraded pre‐disturbance ecosystem we are looking to restore (Rheinhardt et al. 1999)? Further, once we have decided on our model ecosystem, what are the salient features on which restoration should concentrate: functions, species composition, structure, or perhaps all of these (Light and Higgs 1996; Palmer et al. 1997)? And what about our basic reasons for undertaking restoration in the first place? Should we be focusing on the human benefits of restoration, including an increase in our scientific understanding of ecology (Jordan et al. 1987) – in which case one is likely to see significant departure from the initial model – or should our aim be rather that of fidelity to whatever natural model we have selected (Light and Higgs 1996; Egan 2006)?

      That branch of philosophy that deals with our ethical relationship to nature is called “environmental ethics” (Palmer et al. 2014). Within environmental ethics, ecological restoration has been the subject of intense debate ever since the publication of a famous article on the subject by Elliott (1982) entitled “Faking Nature.” Elliott’s basic argument was that one cannot ever fully restore an ecosystem, not because it is a technical impossibility (though it may also be a technical impossibility) but rather because an important value associated with the original ecosystem – the value of naturalness itself, where naturalness is understood in terms of having a genesis independent of human action – is necessarily lost. For Elliott, even when the restoration produces an ecosystem that is so successful that a trained eye would struggle to distinguish it from the original, the result is analogous to a fake work of art, whose value – despite the deceptive precision of the reproduction – is necessarily less than the original.

      Elliott’s critique of ecological restoration was later followed up by Katz, who in a number of articles argued that the assumption – taken as characteristic of restoration ecology in general – that humans can destroy and recreate ecosystems at will is a simple continuation of the traditional anthropocentric goal of dominating and controlling nature (Katz 1996, 1997). Moreover, there are various concrete restoration scenarios that do seem to support Katz’s criticism. One of these is the case on which Elliott’s argument is based: a mining company seeking to use the claim that no value would be lost in the case of a perfect restoration in order to justify the temporary destruction of the obstructing ecosystem in the present – an argument that Elliott (1982, p. 81) calls the “restoration thesis.” Another example is the project of transporting the Zurich Airport wetland by cutting it up into a number of pieces and reassembling them in a different location (Loucks 1994). Similarly, it is not uncommon for streams and rivers to be destroyed and reconstructed elsewhere so as to better fit in with development objectives (Prager and McPhillips 2012). Nature, in all these cases, appears as almost infinitely malleable, as something that can be destroyed to make way for human economic activity, while also being reproduced and even moved around at will.


Скачать книгу