Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience. P. M. S. Hacker

Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience - P. M. S. Hacker


Скачать книгу
Hacker have provided. Even those who fundamentally disagree with their arguments ( and I look forward to seeing them engage in debate) must surely acknowledge that this is a sustained and valuable exposition of an important and influential philosophical position.

      Although I would describe that position as philosophically radical (in the correct sense of that word: going back to basic roots and eradicating those that shouldn’t be there), it is often dismissed by scientists as conservative because it may appear to restrict using language in new ways. Yet, they would argue, science cannot advance without doing that. And what better way to achieve it than to start with metaphor or façons de parler, consolidate with dead metaphor (metaphors that become part of everyday language – constructivists argue that that is the way language evolved) and finally end up with a change in our conceptual scheme? Indeed, why not, if that is what will enlighten us, lead us into new conceptual territory, formulate new theories. But there is a simple test for whether that could work in any particular case. For each such metaphorical (or similar) change in use or meaning, or novel piece of terminology (such as ‘qualia’ or ‘memes’), imagine stating its opposite, and then ask whether any conceivable experiment could test empirically between the two. The deep problem for many ‘novel’ concepts and language uses in reductionist approaches is that this test totally fails. The novel use of language is then not so much a scientific as a political or social tool. If you doubt this, try imagining an experiment to test between the existence or non-existence of qualia. Or for whether or not the brain makes representative maps (which are not homunculi incidentally). Or for brain states that ‘explain’ rational thought (rather than being a necessary physical basis for its existence). Surely we should only introduce new terminology where, as with quarks and black holes, we provide the empirical criteria for determining their existence?

      This is particularly true of rational behaviour, including the use of language. The argument is basically very simple. We cannot, coherently, deny our own rationality. Otherwise we would have difficulty meaning what we say or being convincing in saying it, which is precisely what happens in the sad cases of those mentally ill people who nevertheless are aware of, but can’t help, their irrationality. If we really could succeed in ‘reducing’ rational behaviour simply to molecular or cellular causation then we would no longer be able meaningfully to express the truth of what we had succeeded in doing. But, thankfully, no such reduction is conceivable. We know what it is to be rational, and what it is to lose that capacity. That knowledge has nothing to do with the question whether there exist specific and causally sufficient neural states and interactions while I am writing this review, for example. Of course they do. And, if we can discover them, they may well provide a complete explanation for the mechanisms of my brain while thinking and writing. The main claim of anti-reductionism in science is that such a complete explanation of mechanisms at one level does not necessarily explain what exists and happens at higher levels. Indeed we may need to know about the higher levels in order to explain the lower-level data that form an input to the mechanisms involved (which is what must be the case in writing this review! – one of the inputs was my reading this book, but the book is not thereby ‘inside’ my brain).

      The most spectacular case of this need for higher-level understanding in modern biology is, of course, the genome, whose sequences will only be understood eventually in terms of higher-level function (genes don’t come with functional names attached – nor do neurones!).

      Concurrently I also interacted extensively with professional philosophers (of different schools of thought – including those who would support the reductionist agenda). Coming to adopt an integrationist agenda was not an easy road, either scientifically or philosophically. But it is a far richer position. The integrationist does not deny the validity or immense achievements of successful reduction. For some reason ( political, social, philosophical? ) reductionists seem to need to claim universality for their approach. This book will give them some cause to re-think that position – or so I would hope.

      Notes

      1 1 See, for example, D. Noble, ‘What do intentions do?’, in A. Montefiore and D. Noble (eds), Goals, No Goals and Own Goals ( Unwin Hyman, London, 1989) and D. Noble, ‘Biological explanation and intentional behaviour’, in W. H. Newton-Smith and K. Wilkes (eds), Modelling the Mind ( Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1991).

      2 2 D. Noble, ‘Biological computation’, in Encyclopedia of Life Sciences, http://www.els.net ( Nature Publishing Group, London, 2002); D. Noble, ‘The rise of computational biology’, Nature Reviews Molecular Cell Biology, 3 (2002), pp. 460–3. See also Novartis Foundation, In Silico Simulation of Biological Processes, Novartis Foundation Symposium, vol. 247 ( John Wiley, London, 2002).

       Denis Noble CBE FRS hon FRCP

       Professor of Cardiovascular Physiology at Oxford University

       Secretary-General, International Union of Physiological Sciences (1993–2001)

      In the course of writing this expanded second edition, we have benefited greatly from the advice and constructive suggestions of many friends and colleagues. We are grateful to Hanoch Ben-Yami, Anthony Kenny, Parashkev Nachev, Hans Oberdieck, Juan Pascual, Herman Philipse and Gabriele Taylor. They all read one or more of the new chapters or sections and gave us their helpful comments for which we are much indebted.

      M. R. B.

      P. M. S. H.

      Many people have assisted us in writing this book, and we have benefited from their advice, critical comments and constructive suggestions. We are grateful to Dr Hanoch Benyami, Professor Jonathan Dancy, Professor John Dupré, Dr Hanjo Glock, Professor Oswald Hanfling, Professor Paul Harris, Dr Tim Horder, Professor Andrew Parker, Professor Herman Philipse, Dr John Richardson, Wolfram Schmitt and Professor Stuart Shanker for their helpful comments on one or more (sometimes many more) chapters of the book. We are especially indebted to Dr John Hyman and Professor Hans Oberdiek, who read and commented constructively on the whole text. We thank Sir Anthony Kenny, Professor Sir Peter Strawson and Professor Georg Henrik von Wright for their encouragement and moral support throughout the writing of this book. We are grateful to Jean van Altena for copy-editing our typescript with her characteristic skill, tact and good humour.


Скачать книгу