Dogs in the Leisure Experience. Neil Carr
labelled animals closer to the human family. Yet these values have not always been recognized, leading to the suggestion by Serpell (in Herzog, 2010), among others, that the pet has no function and therefore is without value. This consigns the pet dog to the bottom of the heap where it is not only a mundane animal, but a valueless mundane animal.
Just becoming a pet does not, of course, mean that a dog ceases to be an object or tool. Indeed, as will be discussed in Chapter 4, many dogs have been and still are owned as pets, if not solely then certainly partially, for the displaying of the owners’ wealth and status. This trend, Power (2012) suggested, emerged with the growth of the middle class in western Europe in the 1800s and the growth in dog ownership among this population. The Council for Science and Society (1988: 4) saw this situation having continued into the contemporary era where: ‘Unusual and expensive breeds of dog or cat, for example, may be owned as much for reasons of prestige as for anything else.’ They further pointed out that: ‘Animals kept solely as status symbols are often admired and well looked after, but only as long as the image they project corresponds to the owner’s expectations.’ The construction of pet dogs as symbols of the status and wealth of their owners is something that ensures the continued positioning of the dog by humans as an object or tool. The Council for Science and Society also raised the issue of the pet dog as a play toy, hobby or recreational tool, identifying an emphasis on the dog as object in these instances. However, as part of bringing dogs into the house and out of the traditional working environment they have, thanks to humans, assumed more human characteristics (in a process that identifies all that can be wrong with anthropomorphism) and through this potentially negative minefield have emerged, at least partially, as a creature with rights: a sentient being.
The result, as Rice (1968: 210) noted, was that even by the 1960s in the USA and elsewhere, ‘many pets [especially dogs] are part of the family. Their status may be that of an amusing child, a pleasant companion, an understanding friend, or a loving soul-mate. They receive the attention and affection customarily given to people.’ Such a view was also noted by Mann (1975) and is supported by Joseph (2010) who saw animals functioning increasingly as companions, able to alleviate loneliness, make humans feel loved and loving, and provide a conduit through which social bonds between people may be established. In this way the companion dog, it is possible to suggest, is perceived not as an object, but as a subject (Council for Science and Society, 1988) – a sentient animal. Consequently, there is a ‘relationship’ between a companion dog and human owner, which contrasts with the dog as object, with whom a relationship cannot exist.
While acceptance of the dog as a member of the human family has its origins in North America and north-western Europe, there is evidence to suggest that it is becoming a global trend, with dogs being more commonly seen as family members in such diverse places as Australia and New Zealand, India, China and South-east Asia. This trend and its implications will be discussed throughout the book but particularly in Chapter 7, which is concerned with the dog as human cuisine.
The nature of the relation between dogs and people both influences and is influenced by how the sentience of dogs and hence their ‘rights’ are perceived. Questions of sentience and animal rights will be discussed later in this chapter as they colour the entirety of this book, how it is written and how it will doubtless be perceived by the reader. As we see dogs becoming ever more accepted as members of the human family we have witnessed an increasing discussion of the intimate, platonic bonds that can and do develop between dogs and their human family. These relationships are perceived and displayed as ones where ‘The warmth and depth of the affection a dog can display towards its owners and all members of the family, especially to children, is legendary’ (Reichmann, 2000: 353–354).
Why have we witnessed a growth in the number of dogs living as a member of a human family, often sleeping inside, on or near the humans’ bed; travelling in the family car; and going on holiday with the family? One of the most commonly cited reasons is the supposed affection that dogs display to their family members (Reichmann, 2000). This affection is claimed to be unconditional and honest in a way that is incomparable to that available from most human–human relationships (Reichmann, 2000). It is further suggested that in our post-modern society where people increasingly lead isolated lives, separated from their kin and alienated from their neighbours, dogs offer a source of by affection that is not available elsewhere (Katz, 2003). Such a view is supported by the New Zealand Companion Animal Council (2011), which stated that 53% of New Zealanders acquire a dog primarily for companionship.
Based on the recognition of the dog as a source of companionship and affection it has begun to be viewed as a means of increasing the mental health and well-being of people in general (Miklósi, 2007; Wood et al., 2007; Zilcha-Mano et al., 2012), and elderly (Norris et al., 1999) single people in particular. With specific reference to children, dogs have been identified as an aid to their healthy physical and psychological development (Endenburg and van Lith, 2011). The dog also offers the opportunity and drive to enhance the fitness of the owner through its need for exercise (Brown and Rhodes, 2006; Cutt et al., 2008; Yabroff et al., 2008; Oka and Shibata, 2009; Reeves et al., 2011). The benefits of dog ownership do not, according to Wood et al. (2007) and Messent (1983), accrue only to the pet owner. Rather, dogs have the potential to facilitate positive social interaction between owners and non-dog owners that benefits the wider society through the development of a sense of community. Such a claim is well known to most dog owners whose animals often act as social lubricants and initiators of conversations with other owners. Such benefits assume that all social interactions between dogs and their owners and others are positive, which, unfortunately, is not the case. Despite this, as long as the positive encounters outweigh the negative ones, then the presence of dogs in society can be argued to be positive for social cohesion. Furthermore, the dog may offer security (which is often more imaginary than real with pet dogs who are as likely to invite a stranger into the house as bark threateningly at one), which can be very important for those living by themselves (Gillespie et al., 1996). Overall, as Rogerson (1991) and Herzog (2010: 68) noted, we: ‘bring animals [and particularly dogs] into our lives because they make us feel happier, healthier, and more loved’. The reasons why we bring dogs as pets into our lives undermines the argument that a pet is without function or value; rather they are beyond economic valuing and are certainly not valueless to research either in their own right or in the context of their relations with humans. The result of all these reasons for bringing dogs into our lives is an increasingly close bond between dogs and humans that blurs the distinction between animals and humans and ensures dogs are seen ever more as a member of the family.
The idea that dogs help to ensure the mental and physical well-being of humans, while prominent today, is something that appears to have been in existence since