A Sense-of-Wonderful Century. Gary Westfahl
as any animated narrative over thirty minutes long, perhaps allowing for some aesthetically pleasing exceptions; one might go a bit further and stipulate a narrative that is over sixty minutes long.
A second possible criterion would be the context of original presentation: an animated film could be defined as an animated narrative first presented in theatres as a feature film or as an advertised short subject, or as a film first presented as a television special or a separate DVD or videocassette. In contrast, one supposes, cartoons are those animated narratives which are shown as unannounced introductory adornments to features, as episodes of weekly television series, or as segments of longer films or television programs.
Criteria like these are certainly reasonable, and they may be functional enough to help one decide whether to give a work an entry in an encyclopedia of animated movies, but they also seem rather arbitrary, and perhaps too specific to the cultural contexts of contemporary America and Europe. After all, different eras and different places might have quite different expectations about the proper length of a film, and/or the method of presentation which characterizes a film. A proper definition of an animated movie, I would argue, must involve qualities which are more intrinsic to the films under consideration.
To develop such a definition, I suggest that we turn to the most ancient work of literary criticism, Aristotle’s Poetics, and employ his famous list of the six elements of tragedy, more frequently described as his six elements of drama (since a posited accompanying discussion of the elements of comedy has never been found). These are usually given as:
1. Plot
2. Character
3. Thought
4. Diction
5. Song
6. Spectacle4
Aristotle’s elements can be profitably adapted to serve as the six defining elements of the true animated movie.
That is: an animated movie has a true plot—a narrative with a beginning, middle, and end as Aristotle specified; a narrative with dynamics like rising action leading to a climax; and a narrative that may have subplots, double plots, or other complications. In contrast, a cartoon may be little more than the initial definition of a situation (cat wishes to eat bird, bird wishes to escape cat, etc.) followed by a series of repetitive incidents that continue until the piece reaches the proper length and stops—as best illustrated, perhaps, by the Warner Brothers Road Runner cartoons, which typically abandon even the pretense of a unified narrative.
Second, an animated movie has true characters—creatures or people that audiences can relate to as genuine personalities, often with some degree of depth or complexity. In contrast, the characters in a cartoon may be only ciphers or stereotypes: dogs intent upon chasing cats, cats intent upon chasing mice, hunters intent upon shooting rabbits, and so on.
Third, an animated movie has thought, which in modern terms might be termed a message, a theme, a thesis, or a point. An animated movie, unlike a cartoon, always tries to do more than merely entertain viewers or make them laugh; its story is designed to communicate some potentially important statement about the human (or the sentient) condition, even if it is something as puerile as the admonitions in the Care Bears movies that people must “share their feelings.” A cartoon, however, may simply be a series of amusing vignettes that offer no real message of any significance (beyond, say, that it is undesirable to have a big homely cat eat a cute little bird).
Fourth, an animated movie has diction, or words, as a key element. A mere cartoon may function quite well as a series of speechless events, an essentially silent movie with a musical soundtrack (with the Road Runner cartoons again serving as a good example, since the only words typically found therein are on occasional road signs or labels on boxes from the Acme Company). However, to communicate its genuine plot, genuine characters, and genuine theme, the animated movie must communicate through words—narration, dialogue, or titles.
The fifth criterion seems more debatable, since one might reasonably ask: must an animated movie always have songs? Well, it is undeniable that a vast majority of them do; and even those that do not are invariably accompanied and driven by a prominent and compelling soundtrack, closely tied to plot developments, making music at least seem like an essential element of the animated film. In contrast, cartoons generally have no songs, and the music they include may consist simply of repeated passages of stock music that have no particular relationship to the incidents on the screen.
Finally, a true animated movie does strive for an element of spectacle. Its animation is not the mind-numbing “limited animation” of the United Artists cartoons of the 1950s, or of the innumerable cartoon series where characters keep moving in exactly the same way in front of the same backgrounds. Instead, the animated movie consistently strives to be visually impressive; in particular, whether it’s “Pink Elephants on Parade” in Dumbo (1941), “Under the Sea” in The Little Mermaid (1989), or Moses parting the Red Sea in The Prince of Egypt (1998), an animated movie almost always, I believe, has at least one sequence that is designed to be a “show-stopper,” a visually stunning setpiece.
Thus, a proposed definition of an animated movie might be as follows:
An animated movie, as opposed to a cartoon, is an animated narrative that includes (or at least aspires to include) all six of Aristotle’s elements of drama: a true plot, fully developed characters, a theme or message, language, songs and music, and visual spectacle.
What are the advantages of such a definition?
First, there is the appeal to authority. Any formula that springs out the mind of an editor can readily be attacked as ad hoc or specious; but who can sneer at a definition based on Aristotle? This is also a definition which accords with general perceptions of the animated movie, since it would offer support for the widely accepted belief that Walt Disney’s Snow White and the Seven Dwarfs (1937) represents the first animated film, and it would include almost all of the films that most would wish to consider animated movies. (The exceptions might be Disney’s musical anthology films—Fantasia [1940] Make Mine Music [1946], Melody Time [1948], and Fantasia 2000 [1999], since these lack a unified plot, but one could argue that even these films have a unifying theme—increasing audience exposure to and appreciation for various forms of music—and they do have fully developed narratives embedded within them, like “The Sorcerer’s Apprentice” from Fantasia and “The Whale Who Wanted to Sing at the Met” from Make Mine Music.)
More broadly, a definition like this would be very useful in terms of the larger argument that a reference book on animated movies would need to make. The essential point would be that an animated movie is not simply an overlong cartoon, but is rather a distinct genre. Further, with Aristotle’s support, the book might even maintain that the animated movie, far from being a spurious modern development, actually represents a return to the original and most ancient forms of drama, which were characterized by eclecticism and variety. Thus, in ancient Greece, an evening at the theatre would probably involve a trilogy of tragedies, presenting a familiar mythological story with complex characters, a profound message, a singing chorus, and spectacular effects like the deux ex machina descending from above on an elaborate crane; and everything would conclude with a satirical satyr play filled with jokes. And the approach of including something for everybody has remained central to the animated movies of today. In contrast, one might continue, other contemporary movie genres are more limited, lacking one or more of the Aristotelian elements: Merchant-Ivory costume dramas offer no spectacle, slam-bang action movies have no well-developed characters, serious dramas exclude songs, teen comedies lack any thought or message, and so on.
To make the point most boldly, one could posit that if the ancient Greeks returned to Earth today, they would find something like Beauty and the Beast (1991) or The Prince of Egypt far more like their ancient evenings at the theatre than the other films at the multiplexes. Thus, far from being something to belittle, the animated movie could be valorized as something archetypal, a return to ancient principles of drama, a visual narrative that is more complete and more satisfying than any of the others now available to modern filmgoers.
Now, would such