Statistics and the Evaluation of Evidence for Forensic Scientists. Franco Taroni

Statistics and the Evaluation of Evidence for Forensic Scientists - Franco Taroni


Скачать книгу
of a report, edited by Fienberg (1989), by the Panel on Statistical Assessments as Evidence in the Courts formed by the Committee on National Statistics and the Committee on Research on Law Enforcement and the Administration of Justice of the United States, and funded by the National Science Foundation. Through the use of case studies, the report reviews the use of statistics in selected areas of litigation, such as employment discrimination, antitrust litigation, and environment law. One case study is concerned with identification in a criminal case. Such a matter is the concern of this book, and the ideas relevant to this case study, which involves the evidential worth of similarities amongst human head hair samples, will be discussed in greater detail later (Section 3.5.5). The report makes various recommendations, relating to the role of the expert witness, pretrial discovery, the provision of statistical resources, the role of court‐appointed experts, the enhancement of the capability of the fact‐finder, and statistical education for lawyers.

      Two books that take the form of textbooks on statistics for lawyers are Vito and Latessa (1989) and Finkelstein and Levin (2015). The former focusses on the presentation of statistical concepts commonly used in criminal justice research. It provides criminological examples to demonstrate the calculation of basic statistics. The latter introduces rather more advanced statistical techniques and again uses case studies to illustrate the techniques.

’ (volume 1, p. xvii). Two areas are stressed, which are usually given less emphasis in most statistical textbooks. The first area is concerned with measures of relative or comparative inequality. These are important because many legal cases are concerned with issues of fairness or equal treatment. The second area is concerned with the combination of results of several related statistical studies. This is important because existing administrative records or currently available studies often have to be used to make legal decisions and public policy; it is not possible to undertake further research. Gastwirth (2000) has also edited a collection of essays on statistical science in the courtroom, some of which are directly relevant for this current book and will be referred to as appropriate.

      A collection of papers on Statistics and Public Policy has been edited by Fairley and Mosteller (1977). One issue in the book, which relates to a particularly infamous case, the Collins case, is discussed in detail later (Section 3.4). Other articles concern policy issues and decision making.

      Of further interest is a book (Kadane 2008) explicitly entitled ‘Statistics and the Law’, which considers the question ‘how can lawyers and statisticians best collaborate in a court of law to present statistics in the most clear and persuasive manner?’. With the use of case studies that refer to employment, jury behaviour, fraud, taxes, and aspects of patents, there is clarification of what a statistician and what a lawyer should know for a fruitful collaboration.

      Other recent publications on the interaction between law and statistics are, for example, Dawid et al. (2014), Kadane (2018a,b), Kaye (2017a,b), and Gastwirth (2017).

and against its complement
is equal to the difference of the entropies assuming
and
, respectively. A brief discussion of a frequentist approach and the problems associated with it is given in Section 3.6 (see also Taroni et al. 2016). A general review of the Bayesian approach was given by Fienberg (2006).

      Another approach that will not be discussed here is that of Shafer (1976, 1982). This concerns so‐called belief functions, see Section 3.1. The theory of belief functions is a very sophisticated theory for assessing uncertainty that endeavours to answer criticisms of both the frequentist and Bayesian approaches to inference. Belief functions are non‐additive in the sense that belief in an event

[denoted
] and belief in the opposite of
[denoted
] do not sum to 1. See also Shafer (1978) for a historical discussion of non‐additivity. Further discussion is beyond the scope of this book. Practical applications are few. One such, however, is to the evaluation of evidence concerning the refractive index of glass (Shafer 1982). More recent developments of the role of belief functions in law for burdens of proof and in forensic science with a discussion of the island problem (Section 6.1.6.3) and parental identification are given in Nance (2019) and Kerkvliet and Meester (2016).


Скачать книгу