Risk Assessment. Marvin Rausand

Risk Assessment - Marvin Rausand


Скачать книгу
risk of accidents.

      Remark 5.1 (SFAIRP)

      5.3.2 The ALARA Principle

      ALARA is an acronym for “as low as reasonably achievable,” which is the risk acceptability framework in the Netherlands. The ALARA principle is conceptually similar to ALARP, but does not include any region of broad acceptability. Until 1993, the region of negligible risk was part of the Dutch policy. Subsequently, it has been abandoned on the grounds that all risk should be reduced as long as it is reasonable (Bottelberghs 2000). ALARA has gained a somewhat different interpretation in practice. According to Ale (2005), it is common practice in the Netherlands to focus on complying with the upper limit rather than evaluating the reasonable practicality of further action. The unacceptable region in ALARA is, on the other hand, generally stricter than the one in ALARP, and the risk levels usually end up in the same range.

      5.3.3 The GAMAB Principle

      GAMAB is an acronym of the French expression globalement au moins aussi bon, which means “globally at least as good.” The principle assumes that an acceptable solution already exists and that any new development should be at least as good as the existing solutions. The expression globalement (in total) is important here because it provides room for trade‐offs. An individual aspect may therefore be worsened if it is overcompensated by an improvement elsewhere.

      The GAMAB principle has been used in decision‐making related to transportation systems in France, where new systems are required to offer a total risk level that is globally as low as that of any existing equivalent system. The principle is included in the railway RAMS standard (EN 50126 1999). A recent variant of GAMAB is GAME, which rephrases the requirement to at least equivalent.

      GAMAB is a technology‐based criterion, which means that it uses existing technology as the point of reference. By applying this principle, the decision‐maker is exempted from the task of formulating a risk acceptance criterion because it is already given by the present level of risk (e.g. see Johansen 2010).

      5.3.4 The MEM Principle

      Endogenous mortality means death due to internal or natural causes. In contrast, exogenous mortality is caused by the external influences of accidents. The endogenous mortality rate is the rate of deaths due to internal causes of a given population at a given time. Children between 5 and 15 have the MEM rate, which in Western countries is about images images , per person on average (EN 50126 1999). This means that, on the average, one in a group of 5000 children will die each year. The MEM principle requires any technological system not to impose a significant increase in risk compared to this level of reference.

      According to the railway standard (EN 50126 1999), a “significant increase” is equal to 5% of MEM. This is deduced mathematically from the assumption that people are exposed to roughly 20 types of technological systems. Among these are technologies of transport, energy production, chemical industries, and leisure activities. Assuming that a total technological risk in the size of the MEM is acceptable, the contribution from each system is confined to

      (5.3) equation

      A single technological system thus poses an unacceptable risk if it causes the individual risk to be increased by more than 5% of MEM. It should be emphasized that this criterion concerns the risk to any individual, not only the age group that provides the reference value. Unlike ALARP and GAMAB, MEM offers a universal quantitative risk acceptance criterion that is derived from the MEM rate.

      The MEM principle primarily relies on the technology principle as its basis, in that the criterion is related to existing risk levels.

      5.3.5 Societal Risk Criteria

      In 2001, the UK HSE published the report “Reducing Risks, Protecting People” (HSE 2001), which includes a proposed societal risk criterion which says that for any single industrial installation, “the risk of an accident causing the death of 50 or more people in a single event should be regarded as intolerable if the frequency is estimated to be more than one in five thousand per annum.” This was the first time there had been a widely consulted and published criterion of this type.

      5.3.6 The Precautionary Principle

      The original definition of the precautionary principle is given in principle 15 of the UN declaration from Rio in 1992 (UN 1992):

      Definition 5.4 (Precautionary principle)

      Where there are threats of serious or irreversible damage, lack of full scientific certainty shall not be used as a reason for postponing cost‐effective measures to prevent environmental degradation.

      The precautionary principle is invoked where

       There is good reason to believe that harmful effects may occur to human, animal, or plant health, or the environment.

       The level of scientific uncertainty about the consequences or frequencies is such that risk cannot be assessed with sufficient confidence to inform decision‐making.

      Invocation of the precautionary principle may be appropriate with respect to, for example, genetically modified plants where there is good reason to believe that the modifications could lead to harmful effects on existing habitats, and there is a lack of knowledge about the relationship between the hazard and the consequences. A contrary example is that of the offshore industries, for which the hazards and consequences are generally well understood and conventional assessment techniques can be used to evaluate the risk by following a cautionary approach. Invocation of the precautionary principle is therefore unlikely to be appropriate offshore.

      The European Commission has provided guidance on when and how to use the precautionary principle (EU 2000). Studies have shown that the practical implementation still varies significantly (Garnett and Parsons 2017). The decision when to invoke the principle seems to be poorly defined, and there are indications that less evidence is required if the issue is related to harm to people compared to the environment.

      Example 5.4 (Deliberate release into the environment of GMOs)


Скачать книгу