Innovation for Society. Joëlle Forest

Innovation for Society - Joëlle Forest


Скачать книгу

      1.1. Introduction

      The history of the concept of innovation is a fascinating one. It reveals that, contrary to popular belief, innovation has not always been viewed positively. Plato did not hesitate, in Book VII of Laws, to plead for tradition. Because innovation leads young people to despise what is old and to value what is new, it is, according to him, the worst of scourges for a polis, because it leads to instability. Ironically, “the same people who have challenged innovation for centuries – governments – are the same people who have de-challenged it, making innovation an instrument of economic policy” [GOD 14].

      However, the massification of the production and consumption of innovations is nowadays questionable. What is the function of innovation in modern societies? What kinds of relationships does our modern society have with innovation? And more fundamentally, what innovations do we want for which societies?

      In order to provide some answers to the above questions, this chapter invites us to think about the meaning of innovation. We will thus see that while the question of the meaning of innovation is an old question, over time it has been pushed into the background or even overshadowed by the question of the meaning of innovation for society. This observation will lead us to advocate for the reintegration of the meaning of innovation. The question then arises as to how to proceed. We will then present the Penser le Sens de l’Innovation (P.S.I.) approach (thinking about the meaning of innovation), which emphasizes that the question of meaning must be considered from the points of view of both direction and signification.

      In a society where the injunction to innovate is a permanent one, it is legitimate to ask why it seems necessary to think about the meaning of innovation. To better understand our position, let us go back in time.

      1.2.1. The meaning of innovation: an old question

      1.2.1.1. A positive view of innovation

      The question of meaning is not new. Starting in the late 16th Century, Bacon and Descartes associated the progress of knowledge with that of technology, and the progress of technology with the progressive improvement of the living conditions of people. Indeed, Descartes considers technological progress as the vector of the creation of a new “Garden of Eden” in which poverty, illness and even death can be excluded thanks to human genius:

      As soon as I had acquired some general notions of physics, and as soon as I began to experience them in various specific difficult situations, I noticed how far they could lead, and how they differed from the principles hitherto used, I believed that I could not keep them hidden without sinning greatly against the law which obliges us to procure, as far as it is in us, the general good of all men. For they have shown me that it is possible to attain knowledge that is very useful for life… [DES 37, p. 168].

      Specifically, Descartes advocates knowledge for action, with innovations being considered from the point of view of their contribution to the improvement of the living conditions of humanity:

      This is not only to be desired for the invention of an infinity of artifices, which would make it possible to enjoy, without any difficulty, the fruits of the earth and the conveniences found in it, but mostly for the preservation of health [DES 37, p. 168].

      According to Descartes, technological change is thus associated with the idea of progress through and for collective action. This vision of Progress, with a capital “P”, one might say, culminated in the Age of Enlightenment, a century which claimed to be the time when Progress overcame backward-looking obscurantism. It was a century in which humans no longer experienced history passively but became the subject of this history, substituting God’s place in the order of creation and participating in the design of the world in which they lived. It was a century in which faith in the capacity of humans to act, through reason, to make moral and social ideals concrete in the real world. The French Revolution of 1789 seemed to embody the revolution of Progress taking place. This led Claude-Henri de Rouvroy, Count of Saint-Simon, to affirm that the golden age of humanity was before them and not behind them.

       Source: Wikipedia.org. For a color version of this figure, see www.iste.co.uk/chouteau/innovation.zip

      1.2.1.2. A contested relationship to progress

      However, as early as the 18th Century, the question of limits was raised, of a progress beyond which we had as much to lose as to gain:

      Is it necessary to wrest from nature all that can be obtained from it […]? Is not everything else by chance the extravagance of the species […], that is to say, a sure means of living miserably, taking too much care to be happy? […] When nature has been defeated, the rest is just a display of triumph that costs us more than it gives back. [DID 29, p. 313]

      In short, Diderot raises the question of the meaning of human action, of reasoned progress in the face of individuals, whether scientists or innovators, who do not necessarily master the powers that their minds give them.

      While in the 19th Century there was growing suspicion of the relationship between technological progress, moral progress and the capacity of the latter to contribute to human happiness, World Wars I and II dealt a fatal blow to the very idea of progress when the most developed nations of the world clashed in a conflict in which technology played a key role and became its most deadly in the history of mankind2.

      By the middle of the 20th Century, the break with the idea of progress seemed to be complete. Many intellectuals questioned the lack of knowledge of the transformational power offered by innovations [WIE 59] and denounced the autonomous nature of technology which inevitably had unintended consequences [ELL 54].

      Let us take a concrete example to illustrate the point of view of the philosopher Jacques Ellul. The first urban drainage systems spread to cities in the Middle Ages. The most widely used technique was that of “everything out in the street”3, leading to ill health, epidemics and pestilences. It was not until 1854 that engineer Eugène Belgrand, under the orders of Baron Haussmann, set up a sewer system to convey effluents


Скачать книгу