Value. Frederick Harry Pitts

Value - Frederick Harry Pitts


Скачать книгу
Mercantilism reacted to the shifting political economy of sixteenth- and seventeenth-century colonialism, wherein trade expanded and vast amounts of precious metals were extracted from colonies and transformed into currency. The latter came to convey wealth and prosperity, and the ‘production boundary’ between productive and unproductive was redrawn around ‘whoever bought, owned and controlled’ its supply. Where income was greater than expenditure, an enterprise was deemed productive, and those who drew down on this surplus as consumers without producing were deemed unproductive.8

      The mercantilist understanding of the economy – which reappears today in the return of protectionist nationalisms – suggested that a system of equivalent exchange must always mean, in the words of Francis Bacon, that ‘whatever is somewhere gotten is somewhere lost’, justifying inter-country rivalry on the basis that ‘trade is a zero-sum game’.9 Value is here taken to be something conserved, and, to the extent that the exchange in which it features is conducted with the national currency, containable within the borders of the state from which it arose. Hence, the positive trade balance – back on the lips of the post-liberal right today – comes to represent the conservation and augmentation of the value substance.

      Another element of classical substantialism that crops up in the intellectual imaginary of contemporary populisms of both right and left is the positioning of sections of the economy that are ‘productive’ of value against those that are ‘unproductive’ of value. Such a distinction is intrinsic to theories of value that rest on a ‘conservation principle’. No substantialism can successfully free itself of the presumption of the unproductiveness of one economic activity or another, because ‘the imposition of conservation principles in the context of a substance theory of value essentially dictates the existence of such categories’. The French physiocrats ‘were the first to make the postulation of unproductive sectors a hallmark of their analysis’, and from this it ‘became the hallmark of a substance theory of value’.10

      Assessing the contributions of Boisguillebert and others, Marx attributes to the physiocrats a laudable desire to investigate surplus value and relate it to labour-time, but without having first given thought to the form of value itself. In this way, the physiocrats were guilty of ‘discussing a complex form of the problem without having solved its elementary form’. This led to them ‘confusing the labour which is materialised in the exchange-value of commodities and measured in time units with the direct physical activity of individuals’.14

      Moreover, whilst acknowledging the stratification of society necessary to the system of commodity production, and recognizing the ‘significance of labour’ in his theory of production costs, Smith incorporated labour only insofar as it cast producers as simple owners of commodities who enter the marketplace eager to exchange commodified portions of their own embodied, objectified labour with others. This process was not contextualized within capitalist society, but seen as an expression of ‘direct barter, the spontaneous form of exchange’ intrinsic to the human experience.22 In this ahistorical and asocial fashion, Smith’s analysis centred on the commodity as its key principle, labour’s significance relating only to its role in commodity production and exchange. Hence, it is not as simple as saying a labour ‘substance’ determines value in exchange, but rather there is a two-way process in which the one depends upon the other. This introduces a profound ambivalence in Smith’s value theory.23 The value of a commodity expresses the labour embodied in it, whilst at the same time positing


Скачать книгу