The Truth About Freud's Technique. Michael Guy Thompson

The Truth About Freud's Technique - Michael Guy Thompson


Скачать книгу
employment of a fiction like this is, however, justified when one considers that the infant—provided that one includes with it the care it receives from its mother—does almost realize a psychical system of this kind, (quoted in Rycroft 1968, 102–3)

      Freud might have added to this “fiction” the notion that the infant is virtually helpless before it enjoys the “protection” of its developing ego. Rycroft observes that “Freud’s notion that the primary processes precede the secondary in individual development was dependent on . . . the helplessness of the infant and his having therefore assumed that the mother-infant relationship . . . was one in which the mother was in touch with reality while the infant only had wishes” (103). Again, we are struck by the notion, Freud’s notion, that the infant needs somebody else (in this case, the mother) or, later, an ego, to grapple with reality on its behalf. Rycroft believes that infants aren’t as helpless as they seem: “If one starts from the assumption that the mother is the infant’s external reality and that the mother-infant relationship is from the very beginning a process of mental adaptation, to which the infant contributes by actions such as crying, clinging, and sucking, which evoke maternal responses in the mother, one is forced to conclude that the infant engages in realistic and adaptive behavior.” (103)

      Rycroft concludes that the secondary thought processes probably operate earlier than Freud had supposed, that they even coincide with primary process thinking. Did Freud accurately depict the responsibilities of the two (hypothesized) thought processes in question? Even if he was right in proposing that infants are ruled by the ones he presumed were primary, what if those processes happen to include those very qualities he attributed to the secondary, such as rationality, judgment, and decision making; even an awareness of reality? Wouldn’t such a scenario negate the utility of the ego’s “synthetic” powers? If Freud’s original formulation of the ego is retained—that it is essentially defensive in nature—then the so-called unconscious id, governed by primary thought processes, might be conceived as a form of consciousness. Freud’s wish to distinguish between two types of thinking could be retained, but only after remodelling their capacities and functions. Paradoxically, what I’m suggesting would in many ways reverse Freud’s scheme. The primary thought processes—which I believe are “conscious” but prereflective—enjoy a spontaneous relationship with the world (i.e., reality), whereas the secondary thought processes—those employing the tasks of reflective consciousness—determine the individual’s relationship with himself.

      Rycroft reminds us that, by Freud’s definition, the primary processes aren’t necessarily unconscious, which is to say, without awareness or intentional forethought. He adds that “(a) dreams are conscious; (b) the conscious operation of the primary processes can be observed in (i) various pathological phenomena, notably hysterical dissociated states and fetishistic activity, and (ii) imaginative activity such as play in children and artistic creation in adults” (104).

      The line between the conscious and unconscious is ambiguously blurred in Freud’s characterization of primary and secondary thought process. The idea that children require an intermediary to grapple with reality posed insurmountable logical difficulties that Freud’s increasing reliance on “metapsychological” theories couldn’t resolve. Freud’s characterization of the ego as an agency at odds with three sources of “danger”—the id, the superego, external reality—is consistent with a depiction of secondary processes that are subjected to the demands of reality on the one side and the urges of the id on the other. An ego that has no desires of its own, but that “pop out,” as it were, from the depths of an anonymous otherness could never be truly reconciled with those desires but, as Freud says, could only hope to serve, at best, as “a submissive slave who courts his master’s love. Whenever possible, it tries to remain on good terms with the id” (1961d, 56; emphasis added). Consequently, this hen-pecked and near-helpless ego resigns itself to a position somewhere between the id and reality, whereby “it only too often yields to the temptation to become sycophantic, opportunistic and lying, like a politician who sees the truth but wants to keep his place in popular favor” (56). The “reality principle,” derived from these assumptions, is naturally preoccupied with self-preservation. Given the defensive nature of the ego, even the primary processes pose a threat because after all, it is the primary processes that are thrusting one’s ego into the world.

      Another paradox posed by Freud’s efforts to distinguish between primary and secondary thought process concerns the nature of the so-called irrational and nonsensical thoughts verbalized in the analytic session. If they’re so irrational, how can they be comprehended in terms of egoistic, rational, and scientific ways of thinking? If Freud’s conception of the rational was rooted in causal, scientific explanation, then why did he insist on seeking the unconscious meaning of the neurotic’s dreams and symptoms, rather than their “causes”? By relying on interpretation as his epistemological framework, Freud abandoned science for semantics. This has been noted by others, including Rycroft. If, in fact, we are creatures of semantics and it is language that manifests our symptoms and desires, psychoanalysis no longer relies on scientific rationality to justify its aims—at least not in the way Freud understood science. Rycroft believes that Freud’s insistence on couching psychoanalysis in scientific terms resulted in

      the tendency of classical analytical theory to conceptualize primary process mentation, phantasy, and often even emotion, in terms which suggest that they have an intrinsic tendency to be experienced as alien and intrusive to the self, to describe the primary processes as primitive, archaic, unrealistic, etc., and to treat artistic and religious phenomena as analogues of neurosis. . . . [The ego] has been cast in the mould of the scientist at work, and the normal man implied by theory has been modeled on the rationalist ideal. (1968, 106)

      Perhaps nowhere is the presumed split between desires on the one hand and the capacity to act on them on the other more evocatively described than in Freud’s analogy of the rider on a horse:

      The horse provides the locomotive energy, and the rider has the prerogative of determining the goal and of guiding the movements of his powerful mount towards it. But all too often in the relations between the ego and the id we find a picture of the less ideal situation in which the rider is obliged to guide his horse in the direction in which it itself wants to go. (1964c, 77)

      Freud’s depiction of the normal state of affairs would seem to characterize, instead, the sort of splitting we might ordinarily characterize as pathological, even paranoid. Instead of assigning to the individual a necessary and inevitable fear of the external world that reduces one’s relationships to a capacity for adaptation, why not envision the human infant, as Rycroft suggests, as a creature who starts life in a state of primary integration, by which the infant’s expectations, phantasies, and capacity to perceive are epitomized by something akin to Hartmann’s notion of an “average expectable environment” and Winnicott’s “ordinary devoted mother”? Insofar as the child’s “expectations are fulfilled, primary integration continues . . . and he feels at home in the world” (Rycroft 1968, 111–12). On the other hand, when expectations are thwarted and the child experiences disappointment, the child’s capacities for wishful thinking and adjusting to the environment split off into different realms, or “types,” of thinking. This doesn’t mean, however, that the one type of thinking doesn’t “know” what the other is doing, or that ignorance, however pleasing, reigns supreme.

      The nature of subjectivity has always puzzled philosophers and psychologists alike. Freud’s depiction of an “unconscious” agency whose purpose requires interpretation was his singular contribution to our age. But his theories could never explain what his intuition could actually see. Freud hypothesized some sort of self, or agency, prior to the formation of the ego. This was supported by his theory of primary thought processes and, in another context, by his conception of a primary form of narcissism (see chapter 5). We know that the id is capable of thought because, after all, it “decided” to form an extension of itself—the ego—to insulate itself against the anxiety of being in the world.

      In practical terms, the division between the id and the ego is a false one. As Freud himself emphasized, the ego is merely an “outer layer” of the id—it was never conceived as a separate entity. If we want to be consistent with the ego’s origins, then that ego—following Freud’s reasoning—is nothing


Скачать книгу