Migration and Political Theory. Gillian Brock
what means a government may use to enforce its immigration laws. For instance, may states separate children from their parents at the border if this is an effective way to get migrants to leave or not come in the first place? What criteria should we use in deciding what are the permissible and impermissible ways to enforce immigration policies?
A second core set of questions involves our responses to unjust immigration policies or laws. We center the analysis around questions such as: Are sanctuary cities to be commended? Is it permissible to resist unjust immigration law? What forms of resistance, if any, might be justified in cases of unjust migration policy? Can people smuggling ever be permissible in response to unjust immigration policies?
I then move on to discuss three further important contemporary challenges. It is widely assumed that immigration policy is a matter for nation-states to decide rather than smaller political sub-units. Should cities be permitted to make their own immigration policies? If so, what sorts of decisions might they rightfully make for themselves? Next, we look at some of the important critiques emerging from critical border studies theorists. For instance, such theorists argue that once we connect processes that drive movement within the state with drivers across state borders, we see a number of common elements that should be studied and tackled together. Powerful multinational corporations have shaped migration through foreign investment, activities, and structural processes, that drive both intrastate movements (such as from rural to urban environments) and movements from low-income to high-income countries. If we wish to tackle some of the most important drivers of movement around the planet that force vulnerable people from their homes, we must appreciate the role that structural processes and powerful actors play.
The chapter then proceeds to analyze how the emergence of the Covid-19 pandemic might affect political theorizing about migration in the future. The chapter concludes by briefly explaining why the recently adopted UN Global Compacts on migration might become important policy instruments that can help guide improved global migration governance in the future and why this would constitute significant progress.
1 * Getting accurate data on migrants can be tricky because not all countries use the same definition of who counts as an international migrant. While a common account involves defining migrants as those who have changed their country of usual residence, some children who have never migrated are counted in these statistics.
2 The Right to Exclude and Open Borders
Millions of people attempt to immigrate every year. And states are highly selective in deciding whom to include, denying membership to many. Would-be migrants frequently take extreme measures to enter anyhow, such as by paying people smugglers large sums of money to hide them in refrigerated containers or transport them in overcrowded boats, sometimes with tragic results. In a recent prominent case, in October 2019, 39 deceased Vietnamese were found in a sealed refrigerated van in Essex, United Kingdom, having begun their journey in distant lands and traveling through Europe.*
Most high-income states adopt very restrictive policies concerning admissions. One central question we examine in this chapter is: Should states be more generous in allowing would-be immigrants into their territory, so that they admit higher numbers than they currently do? We begin by focusing on the core questions that have dominated the literature: May states permissibly deny admission to any and all persons who would like to immigrate to their state, more or less as they see fit, and permissibly adopt a “closed borders” position should they so choose? By contrast, are they obliged to open their borders more than they currently do?
Those who argue in favor of more freedom of movement across borders often draw on two common lines of argument. One concerns massive injustice and inequality in the international sphere. Consider how people across the globe experience vast disparities in life prospects. Some states are incapable of providing even the most basic goods and services, such as clean water and safe sanitation, necessary for a decent life. Others seem to provide the essentials for a good life relatively reliably for almost all citizens. States vary greatly in the opportunities they can make available, including the opportunities for reasonably well-paid jobs, educational attainment, healthcare, and life expectancy. Those states that can offer such prospects are often thought to be desirable destinations and constitute considerable pull factors. And there are many relevant push factors as well that drive people to leave their countries of origin, searching for greener pastures. These include high levels of violence, dysfunctional or repressive governments, and civil war. So, because prospects for good lives are not evenly distributed across the world, this provides at least one dominant motivation for why some might seek to move.
This brings us to a second common consideration in favor of opening borders, which concerns human freedom and the right to free movement. Among the important values that we often think states should respect are people’s freedoms, especially their freedom of movement. If states restrict entry to their territory, are they violating an important freedom? Would they be violating a human right that people should enjoy?
Michael Walzer and Joseph Carens have been especially influential in debates on these issues of how open or closed our borders should be. They deserve a special focus, given that their arguments have largely set the terms for much contemporary debate, and as they offer opposing views, they will anchor the two central parts of this chapter.
Walzer starts from the idea that existing political communities can have important value. Self-determination, which is an essential part of sustaining a flourishing political community, therefore deserves special weight. His argument supports states’ rights to restrict immigration, though he also argues for important limits on such rights. Carens also allows for some permissible restrictions, such as when large numbers of entrants might threaten public order, safety or security, though it is also clear that Carens believes there are limits to arguments for restrictions on these grounds and, in general, borders should be far more open. In comparing these two positions, Walzer is arguing for relatively strong rights to control borders and to exclude. Carens, by contrast, argues for much weaker rights to control borders, and for us to take the interests of the global disadvantaged more seriously. Many who choose to leave their communities have very good reasons for wanting to exit, such as poverty, persecution, and oppression. Carens argues that we need to give those reasons more weight than we currently do in our admissions policies. While these two theorists ground the contrasting positions, we also consider the influential arguments of others who argue for similar conclusions but from very different perspectives.
2.1 Arguments for states’ rights to exclude
In this section, I discuss theorists who defend and prioritize a reasonably strong right to self-determination, that is, the right to decide matters that crucially affect them as a political community.* On their view, immigration can certainly be one of these issues. So, on this line of thought, a political community has a right to decide who to admit, how many to admit, how open or closed its borders should be and other core issues related to migration, such as controlling the shape of cultural change in their country through immigration. There is no general duty for states to open their borders. Those who defend such views include Michael Walzer (1983), David Miller (2016), and Charles Taylor (1994). Michael Walzer offers a classic defense of the position and so we begin with him. We then discuss some of the other accounts that have been offered in support of the view, including arguments that heavily weight the importance of freedom of association, the ownership of our political institutions, and those that are united in their concern for the costs of opening borders.
2.1.1 Walzer, self-determination and protecting the character of communities
Walzer starts from the important idea that states are (or should be) self-determining communities and that