Ethics at the Heart of Higher Education. Группа авторов

Ethics at the Heart of Higher Education - Группа авторов


Скачать книгу
achieve their end no matter what that end might be. This procedure is to my mind deeply flawed. Although it might appear to honor each student’s particular history and refuse to impose moral norms on them, it actually does the reverse. The assumption that ethics is about an autonomous decision to choose your own way of life and pursue it consistently is one ethical option among others. To assume that a course should proceed along these lines is to narrow down ethical possibilities, not expand them. It also neglects the inevitable link between ethics and politics. The answer to the question of a well-lived life will assume some underlying social formation that is worthy of our lives.

      Normative ethical judgments should not be imposed on students, but how one teaches them without imposition—implicit or explicit—is exceedingly difficult. I once had an ethics teacher who was well known for beginning his course by stating, “In this class you do not have minds to make up for yourself about ethics. Your purpose is to think like me.” Most students were immediately appalled and raised their resistance to whatever he said next. His purpose was to challenge the default position of emotivism that he found among students, as if whatever they felt or thought about ethics was somehow in itself sufficient to the task. He did not say that students were to arrive at the same normative judgments that he did, although I think he hoped they would. He stated that they should follow a way of thought that he had inherited from others in order to think better about ethics. Part of that way of thought was to recognize that living one’s life for wealth, pleasure, honor, or health was insufficient for human flourishing, and to trust those forms of social life whose end was wealth, pleasure, honor or health alone were insufficient for one’s loyalty. Another part was to dissuade students that ethics was a pursuit of individual preference. These two parts are, however, negative. They tell us what should not to be done, not what should be done. Can we do more than this?

      What is a well-lived life? What is human flourishing? What is the purpose for human existence? If ethics is to become more than a description of the diverse ethical sources student already have, and engage the normative task present in the second assumption, then it cannot avoid these questions. No single answer to the purpose for ethics suffices in the university, but below are ten well-known possible answers.

      1.The purpose of ethics is to maximize utility.

      2.The purpose of ethics is to honor and respect the dignity of every individual.

      3.The purpose of ethics is to cultivate virtue in order to be a loyal citizen.

      4.The purpose of ethics is happiness, learned within a context of friends.

      5.The purpose of ethics is to obey Torah.

      6.The purpose of ethics is to submit to Allah.

      7.The purpose of ethics is to love the Blessed Trinity, enjoy God forever and in so doing love one’s neighbors and enemies.

      8.Ethics has no purpose. It only expresses subjective values or preferences of approbation or disapproval.

      9.Ethics is a practical skill to match means to ends whatever end one chooses for one’s self.

      10.Ethics is nothing but a disguised form of power by which the privileged take advantage of those without privilege.

      Let me offer a brief commentary on each of these possible answers. The first two are the dominant forms ethics takes in the modern university. They assume an isolated individual as the basic subject of ethical action, and provide a formal, putatively universal account of ethics. They tend to be reductive. The first answer makes individuals into utility maximizers, but no discrimination is made about the content of utility. The second also assumes the basic subject for ethics is the individual, but rather than a utility maximizer, the individual is now a rights bearing entity whose rights should be respected by all other rights bearing entities. It too is formal in that it does not attempt to give content to those rights. The first option is an ethics for the marketplace; the second for modern democratic nation-states. Both options do not take a person’s history as her or his moral starting point, but abstract from it by reducing persons to individuals.

      To this point, I have not made a case for a religious ethic, whether it be Jewish, Christian or Islamic, but only attempted to question if a secular ethic should be given the default position as it often is in the modern university. Like religious ethics, it too should have to give an account of itself—tell us what it is, what purpose it serves, and why it will let us flourish as human beings more so than other kinds of ethics. What account might a religious ethics give for itself? At a minimal level, anyone who seeks to be conversant with the ethics of the vast majority of the earth’s inhabitants should at least be aware of the ethical teachings among the world’s religions. Because each religion has contested teachings on ethics, it would behoove us to encourage the religious persons with whom we inhabit this world to be the best representatives of that religion’s teachings. For instance, I think it is preferable to encourage the world’s religions at least to take seriously their just war traditions over holy crusades. For that matter, a secular war ethics would benefit from the practical wisdom of the just war tradition.

      Beyond this minimal reason for teaching religious ethics is the important ethical question of whether or not God exists, and what it matters in everyday life. For if there is a God, and a God like the transcendent deity at least in part shared among the Abrahamic faiths, then God is not one more object


Скачать книгу