Sociology. Anthony Giddens

Sociology - Anthony Giddens


Скачать книгу
‘bear down disproportionately on the poor’ (Agyeman et al. 2003: 1).

      An important foundational campaign was that of Lois Gibbs in Niagara Falls, New York, in 1978, who sought to relocate the Love Canal community, which she discovered had been built on a 20,000-ton toxic chemical dump. The community campaign was ultimately successful when 900 working-class families were relocated away from the leaking dump in 1980 (Gibbs 2002). Linking environmental quality to social class inequalities shows that environmentalism is not just a middle-class concern but can be related to working-class interests and takes account of social inequalities and real-world ‘risk positions’. In the USA, toxic waste sites have tended to be situated in black and Hispanic communities, where citizens’ action groups are relatively less powerful, but Gibbs’s working-class campaign showed that they are not powerless.

      Environmental justice groups can be very significant. Their emergence has the potential to broaden the support base of environmental politics to currently under-represented groups within the wider environmental movement. For instance, Friends of the Earth International (among others), recognizing the need to tackle social problems if pressures on the natural environment are to be relieved (Rootes 2005), has expanded its agenda. Environmental justice takes us into the urban and inner-city areas, where most of the waste products of modern life wind up, and this opens environmental politics to people who may not have thought about their problems as being at all ‘environmental’.

      Perhaps the most significant consequence of environmental justice groups is that they offer the possibility of linking environmental politics across the developed and developing societies. An important example was the protest against the impact of the multinational oil company Shell on the environment of the indigenous Ogoni people in Nigeria. The campaign of the Movement for the Survival of the Ogoni People (formed in 1990) and the international support it garnered is just one example of the potentially unifying concept of environmental justice. Attempts by the Nigerian government to put down the resistance movement involved torture, ransacking of villages and, in 1995, the execution of nine members of the movement’s leadership, including the writer Ken Saro-Wiwa, in the face of international protest (Watts 1997).

      One final development worthy of note is the emergence of a proposed form of citizenship linked to the defence of the natural environment. Some sociologists and political scientists have argued that a new form of citizenship is emerging, which M. J. Smith (1998) has called ecological citizenship and Dobson and Bell (2006) refer to as environmental citizenship.

gril

      See chapter 11, ‘Poverty, Social Exclusion and Welfare’, for more on citizenship.

      Ecological citizenship is a fourth stage of citizenship beyond the existing civil, political and social types, involving new obligations: to non-human animals, to future generations of human beings, and to maintaining the integrity of the natural environment (Sandilands 1999). Obligations to animals means reconsidering human uses of animals that infringe their right to lead a natural life and express their natures. Hence, vivisection, hunting, farming methods, breeding and even pet-keeping would all need to be reassessed. Ecological citizenship’s obligation to future generations of people means working towards sustainability over a long time period. If economic development plans threaten the ability of future generations to provide for their own needs, then other forms will need to be designed and planned. Political and economic planning must become future-oriented and take a long-term view rather than adopting a short-term, free-market or laissez-faire approach. Finally, all human activity should be considered with reference to its effects on the natural environment, and a precautionary principle should be adopted that puts the onus on developers to justify their actions in ecological terms.

      In essence, ecological citizenship introduces a new demand for people to take account of their ‘ecological footprint’ – the impact of human activity on the natural environment. Clearly, ecological citizenship demands some fundamental changes to modern societies. Perhaps the most radical change would be to people themselves, as ecological citizenship requires a transformed human experience of nature and the self as tightly bound together. In the same way that people had to start to perceive themselves as citizens with rights in order for political citizenship to take hold, so ecological citizenship is unlikely to develop fully unless people’s identities also include the experience of having an ‘ecological self’.

      Geologists call the period of Earth history following the glacial retreat of the last ‘Ice Age’ the Holocene, which covers the last 12,000 years. In the twenty-first century, some scientists now argue that we have left the Holocene behind and moved into a new epoch known as the Anthropocene (Crutzen and Stoermer 2000). As the name suggests, the Anthropocene is a period in which human activity has become the dominant force shaping ecosystems and the global climate, and which will be identifiable in the geological record. It seems clear that the concept is closely tied to scientific evidence of anthropogenic climate change and its impact.

      Although the Anthropocene is an emerging concept that is by no means accepted by all, it has brought into sharp focus the issue of human ‘stewardship’ of the Earth. Even if we accept that human societies have brought about a new era, this was not a planned development but the consequence of industrial capitalist evolution and the constant pressure for economic growth, however environmentally damaging that might be. Should we accept that human beings are now stewards of the planet with all the responsibility that brings, or do we work to radically reduce the human impact on the planet in order to preserve a distinct, independent world of nature? Theorists of the Anthropocene argue that the latter option has already been bypassed. There is no longer a ‘nature’ separate from humanity.

      Today we are able to acknowledge the dark side of modern industry, technology and science, which the classical sociologists could not have foreseen. Scientific and technological developments have created a world of high-consequence risks that make possible both huge gains and losses. Yet, with a growing global human population, the idea that a majority of people could ‘go back’ to living more ‘natural’ lives in close contact with the land is patently


Скачать книгу