The Herodotus Encyclopedia. Группа авторов

The Herodotus Encyclopedia - Группа авторов


Скачать книгу
Konstruktionen von autonomía bei Herodot und Aristophanes.” Antike und Abendland 49: 14–35.

      6 Wells, Joseph. 1923. Studies in Herodotus. Oxford: Blackwell.

      FURTHER READING

      1 Dover, K. J. 2004. “The Limits of Allegory and Allusion in Aristophanes.” In Law, Rhetoric and Comedy in Classical Athens: Essays in Honour of Douglas M. MacDowell, edited by D. L. Cairns and R. A. Knox, 239–49. Swansea: Classical Press of Wales.

      CHRISTOPHER BARON,

       University of Notre Dame

      Patronymic, father of COBON (6.66.2). Herodotus names Cobon as the man who wielded the greatest influence at DELPHI in the first decade of the fifth century BCE. Nothing more is known of Aristophantus.

      CHRISTOPHER BARON

       University of Notre Dame

      King or perhaps TYRANT of TARENTUM (Taras) in southern ITALY in the late sixth century BCE. Herodotus recounts how, when the Greek doctor DEMOCEDES reached Italy with a Persian scouting expedition during the reign of DARIUS I, Aristophilides helped Democedes escape to CROTON by removing the steering oars from the two Persian ships and placing the crews under arrest (3.136.2). Aristophilides, whom Herodotus labels basileus, is not attested in other sources, which are admittedly thin for southern Italy in the ARCHAIC AGE. Tarentum was ruled by a DEMOCRACY in the mid‐fifth century, but as a colony of SPARTA it is possible the city originally had a king (see Malkin 1994, 132, though the date of the episode Herodotus narrates cannot be “492”; it must be earlier than Darius’ Scythian expedition (cf. 3.139.1, 3.150.1, and 4.1.1), thus c. 515 BCE). But it is also possible that Herodotus’ term refers to a magistracy, not a kingship (Jacquemin 1993, 21 n. 24).

      SEE ALSO: Colonization; Gillus; Monarchy; Ships and Sailing

      REFERENCES

      1 Jacquemin, Anne. 1993. “Oikiste et tyran: fondateur‐monarque et monarque‐fondateur dans l’Occident grec.” Ktèma 18: 19–27.

      2 Malkin, Irad. 1994. Myth and Territory in the Spartan Mediterranean. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

      SUSAN D. COLLINS

       University of Notre Dame

      Writing in the century after Herodotus, Aristotle refers to him directly only a few times in his works. Although these references show that Aristotle had read and was willing to make use of the Histories, they do not definitively establish his view of the work. His most definitive statement occurs in the Poetics. There he identifies Herodotus as an “historian” just prior to introducing his well‐known distinction between history (historia) and poetry (poiēsis): history speaks of what has come to be, whereas POETRY speaks of the sort of things that could come to be (what is likely or necessarily to happen). On this account, poetry is both more philosophic and more serious than history, since poetry speaks more of general things and history of particular things (Pol. 1451a36–51b7). The immediate difficulty is that Aristotle’s statement assumes the disciplinary divisions of the fourth century BCE, a development for which Aristotle himself deserves much credit. Hence, it would seem that the classification of Herodotus as an historian is anachronistic, since, in writing in the fifth century, he is not confined by later disciplinary lines.

      Some scholars argue that Aristotle is not just critical of Herodotus, but actively hostile to his approach. Others not only dispute this view but suggest that Aristotle may not necessarily be denying philosophic seriousness to the Histories, a work which, after all, investigates “causes” (aitiai) and provides a “reasoning” (LOGOS). Indeed, we see that in another direct reference to the Histories, in his Constitution of Athens, Aristotle virtually imitates Herodotus’ way of writing in offering without comment two stories, including one from Herodotus, regarding a particular event: the tyrant PEISISTRATUS’ return to ATHENS and the trick MEGACLES (II) used to persuade the people of Athens that this return had divine sanction (Ath. pol. 14.4). There is no doubt that Aristotle diverges from Herodotus on the relation of history to PHILOSOPHY and the quest for wisdom, but perhaps in this way, he nods in the direction of the “historian” and the “ancient way” of treating human affairs by acknowledging the difficulty of inquiring into these affairs, which are by their very nature particular, disputable, and subject to CHANGE and fortune (see also Eth. Nic. 1094b11–18, 1100a5–11).

      SEE ALSO: Hellenistic Historians; Historical Method; historiē; Knowledge; Reception of Herodotus, Ancient Greece and Rome; Rhetoric; Scholarship on Herodotus, Ancient Greece and Rome; Thurii

      FURTHER READING

      1 Benardete, Seth. 1969. Herodotean Inquiries. The Hague: M. Nijhoff. Reprint, South Bend, IN: St. Augustine’s Press, 2009.

      2 De Ste. Croix, G. E. M. 1992 [1975]. “Aristotle on History and Poetry.” In Essays on Aristotle’s Poetics, edited by Amélie Oksenberg Rorty, 23–32. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

      3 Dewald, Carolyn, and John Marincola, eds. 2006. The Cambridge Companion to Herodotus. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (See especially the chapters by Marincola, Fowler, Griffin, Thomas, Luraghi, Bakker, and Hornblower.)

      4 Goldhill, Simon. 2002. The Invention of Prose. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

      5 Gomme, A. W. 1954. The Greek Attitude to Poetry and History. Berkeley: University of California Press.

      6 Hartog, François. 1988. The Mirror of Herodotus: The Representation of the Other in the Writing of History, translated by Janet Lloyd [first French edition 1980]. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.

      7 Momigliano, Arnaldo. 1958. “The Place of Herodotus in the History of Historiography.” History 43: 1–13. Reprinted in ORCS Vol. 1, 31–45.

      8 Thompson,


Скачать книгу