The Power In The Land. Fred Harrison

The Power In The Land - Fred Harrison


Скачать книгу
But he then proceeded to intimidate future generations of lawmakers in Congress by attacking as a ‘wicked project’ any attempt at an ‘equal division of property’.7 By failing to specify how to deal with the most serious problem in civil society — ‘the unequal distribution of property’—he immediately preached against a philosophy that might have produced a fiscal policy to neutralise the consequences. And so the New World, populated by refugees on the run from the old tyrannies that were built on the enclosure of common lands, began to recreate those very conditions that had led to the exodus from Europe (see Chapter 10).

      What of the canons of taxation provided by Adam Smith? These are generally regarded as profound, and are still cited by free market economists as the guidelines for fiscal policy. But as we shall see in Chapter 2, Adam Smith suffered from the shortcoming that led him to a set of prescriptions which prove, to the present author’s satisfaction at least, that he lacked that ‘most exact impartiality’ which Madison considered to be crucial to the making of tax laws. What, then, do we propose as a third alternative to the limited choice at present on offer from right-wing Conservatives and their opponents, the Marxists ?

      Henry George’s analysis culminated in a condemnation of land speculation. He advocated a single tax to capture all economic rent for the community’s benefit, and the simultaneous elimination of taxes on labour and capital. President Reagan was not ideologically disposed to carry out the full Georgist fiscal programme, however: he had made a million himself out of Californian land deals!

      Henry George was called The Prophet of San Francisco. The label was appropriate. He was a fine orator, and his book was written with an unmistakable passion which fired the imaginations of people around the world who sought a practical philosophy which would enable them to both preserve individual liberty and yet restore that primitive cohesion which is vital to a healthy society. The message in Progress and Poverty was a simple one. Natural resources have no cost of production, they are God-given, and so they legitimately belong to everyone. The most efficient way of securing a fair distribution of resources is through a tax on land values. Every citizen has a stake in the revenue which then flows into and out of the exchequer coffers. If the government levies that tax and spends the money on socially-necessary projects, there is no need to interfere with the liberties, economic activities or property of anyone; people know what they want and are capable of securing these for themselves provided that there is no monopoly of land.

      Here we shall try to ignore the ethical arguments (not always successfully, as some of the language will reveal). Our purpose is to explore the scientific proposition that land monopoly, and not the free market, must accept the blame for the poverty and human degradation in industrial society.

      The enquiry necessarily begins with the ‘bible’ of the free market, Adam Smith’s The Wealth of Nations. This was the book that provided the captains of industry and the politicians in Westminster (a body largely composed of landowners) with the theoretical framework and moral justification for the new mode of production. What we discover is that the advocates of capitalism failed to elaborate a scheme that would enable them to attain capitalism’s full potential. So for two hundred years the entrepreneurs and their employees have laboured within the framework of an impure model.

      This has served the Marxist critics well, for they have been able to attack the laissez faire ideal by marshalling evidence derived from a seriously malfunctioning system. That they were pointing to a crippled capitalism has not been an argument used in defence of the free market.

      We, in defending the need to establish laissez faire, maintain that land monopoly is not one of its intrinsic characteristics. The private appropriation of the value of land (as opposed to secure individual possession and use of specific sites) is not a necessary condition for the capitalist mode of production. Capitalism entails the accumulation of wealth based on the provision of goods and services to consumers. It is a two-way exchange: consumers produce wealth in order to exchange it with others — to consume. Land monopoly undermines this creative process because it is a one-way relationship. The monopolist secures legal title to the resources of nature, and then claims a portion of the wealth created by others in return for nothing more than the permission to use land. This is the economics of the bandit sanctified by law. The monopolist per se does not contribute to production; he is, therefore, an anomalous feature within an otherwise efficient system.