This Is Epistemology. J. Adam Carter

This Is Epistemology - J. Adam Carter


Скачать книгу
the parts of a web into parts, isolating the foundations and distinguishing them from the superstructure. In a web, every part is supported by the other parts, and every part lends its support to the structure as a whole.

      1.49 If coherentists wants to convince us that our justified beliefs are justified because they cohere with each other, they need to show that the beliefs that provide rational support for our beliefs derive their justification exclusively from further beliefs, and not from anything located outside the circle of belief. If they don't, there will always be that nagging feeling that some of the justificatory work is done by intuition, experience, testimony, or something outside the circle of belief.

      1.50 An example should help to make this worry vivid. Imagine we are playing a game in which your friend places something on a platter, covers it with a silver cloche, and lifts the cloche with a flourish so that you can see what's on the platter. Before your friend lifts the silver cloche, you have no beliefs at all about what's on the silver platter. (For all you know, it could be anything small enough to fit under a cloche, from a battery to a coin to a piece of cheese.) After the reveal, everything changed – there's a tomato! You quickly came to believe that the thing on the platter was a tomato. Let's suppose that that's all you came to believe and let's suppose that you didn't just believe that the thing on the platter was a tomato. Let's suppose that you knew that it was and so justifiably believed that it was.

      1.51 If this is a plausible description of what happens, we have the makings of a good objection to coherentism:

       Isolation Objection

      P1.The belief that the object is a tomato couldn't be justified before the reveal.

      P2. The belief that the object is a tomato could be justified after the reveal.

      P3. difference in justification is a normative difference.

      P4. If there is a normative difference between beliefs formed before and after the reveal, there must be some further difference between the beliefs that accounts for this normative difference.

      C1. There must be some further difference between the beliefs formed before and after the reveal that accounts for this difference in justification before and after the reveal.

      P5.According to the coherentist, the only difference between beliefs that could account for a difference in justification is how well they cohere with the rest of the believer's beliefs.

      P6.The belief that the object is a tomato coheres with the rest of the subject's beliefs equally well before the reveal and after it.

      C2.Thus, if coherentism is true, then there is no difference between the beliefs formed before and after the reveal that could account for the relevant difference in justification before and after the reveal.

      The crucial point is this. Prior to the reveal, the belief that the object is a tomato wasn't supported by other beliefs. (You might have had good reason to think something would be under the cloche, but you didn't have good enough reason to believe that it was a tomato, a fruit, something red, etc.) When the tomato was revealed, there was a short time when your beliefs stayed the same but your experiences changed. It's only when there's a difference in your experience that we think that you're in a position to justifiably judge that the object is a tomato. It's worth emphasizing that what changes here and seems to account for the fact that you are now in a good position to judge that it's a tomato on the plate is your experience, not your beliefs. Thus, while it might seem to you that something of great significance changed when your experience changed, there's nothing that the coherentist can appeal to in trying to explain why it's a consequence of the reveal and the experience of the tomato that you can now justifiably judge the object to be a tomato.

      1.53 But even if the coherentists said this, it wouldn't get them out of the jam. Suppose that you were playing this game with a friend. Upon seeing the tomato, you spontaneously formed these (allegedly) mutually supporting beliefs:

      1 This looks like a tomato. This is a tomato.

      1.54 Your friend, let's suppose, formed these beliefs:

      1 This looks like a lemon. This is a lemon.

      1.55 Now, we're not supposing that your friend suffered from some sort of illusion or hallucination. They had an experience indistinguishable from yours. We're not supposing that they're confused about how tomatoes and lemons look. We're also not supposing that you've shared your answers yet. You spontaneously judge that the beliefs in (1) are correct, and your friend spontaneously judges that the beliefs in (2) are correct. It's surely possible for one's beliefs to fail to “match” one's experience and for one to fail to notice this. Suppose that such a mistake is what happened in the case of your friend's assessment of the fruit in plain view.

      1.56 Yours and your friend's sets of beliefs are equally coherent. Thus, from the perspective of coherentism, there are no grounds for saying that your beliefs are better justified than your friend's beliefs. And yet it seems that there's a clear difference between your beliefs, and that your beliefs are better justified than theirs. This is a different normative difference from the one we started with, and it doesn't look like the coherentist can account for this difference.

      1.58 We didn't need perceptual beliefs to make the point. The point could have been made equally well using introspective beliefs, the beliefs you form straight off about your own mental life. And, indeed, such an introspective example is offered by Ernest Sosa, in his famous paper “The Raft and the Pyramid” (1980). Consider this passage, in which Sosa poses the following thought experiment:

      Thus take my belief


Скачать книгу