This Is Epistemology. J. Adam Carter
in front your face. What do you see? It looks just like a hand. On the assumption that ambient lighting conditions are normal and that you're not drugged or otherwise mentally incapacitated, it's plausible to suppose that whatever the conditions for knowing a proposition are (e.g. whatever a correct solution to the above “S knows that p if and only if ___” puzzle would be) you surely satisfy these conditions when you're looking at your hand in broad daylight at point‐blank range.
I.8 Now, here's where the skeptic comes in. The skeptic begins by inviting us to consider what initially will sound like a ridiculous scenario (these scenarios get called “skeptical hypotheses”). Let's work with this one:
Simulation
Although you think things are mostly normal, and that you're looking at your hand (while intermittently reading the Introduction of an epistemology book), you're wrong; you are in fact a handless brain in a vat, whose every experience is controlled by a computer program designed by an evil scientist. The computer is right now implementing a phase of its program which requires you to suffer the illusion of having a hand and holding it up in front of your face.8
If the situation described in Simulation (rather than what you think is going on) is what's really going on, then, obviously, your belief “Here is a hand” is not true but false. And here's why this matters for your present situation: since you can't know your hand is in front of you right now unless your hand really is in front of you, then it looks like you can't know that your hand is in front of you unless you know that you are not currently in the situation described by Simulation.9 But – and this is where things get sticky – can you really know that you're not in that scenario? You might try pinching yourself as a “test.” But a moment's reflection indicates that that's not a good test: after all, if Simulation were true, then it would seem exactly like you were pinching yourself even if you weren't. A bit more sober reflection indicates this point generalizes to other things we might try to do as tests, which suggests we can't very effectively appeal to any of our experiences in order to satisfactorily rule out the Simulation hypothesis. But if you can't appeal to your experiences as a way of ruling out the Simulation hypothesis, then how exactly can you know it doesn't hold? And – as the skeptic then asks – if you can't know that this situation (incompatible with your having a hand) isn't the situation that's actually playing out right now, then how can you know you have a hand (or, for that matter, any of the other empirical propositions you take yourself to know)?
I.9 We don't mean to upset the reader here. Perhaps you can figure out a way to know you're not a handless brain in a vat, and if that's the case, then all's good. We mention the thought experiment only as a way of showing how the matter of the scope of human knowledge is a question of interest to epistemologists: we think we surely have some knowledge, but proving this in an intellectually respectable way seems to require that we have something compelling to say in response to challenges from the skeptic, and that's easier said than done.
I.10 Let's take a step back and regroup. You, the reader, will now hopefully have some idea what an epistemologist is getting at when he/she tells you that epistemology is about the “nature and scope of human knowledge.” The only problem is that epistemology is about way more than just that. (And if an epistemologist tells you otherwise, they're lying!)
I.11 It's a bit tricky to explain exactly what else epistemology is without simply showing you. And so, This Is Epistemology is our best attempt to do just this – to show you. We have selected 11 key “subtopics” that epistemologists often argue with each other about, and in each case, we do our best to tell all sides of the story. Whether or not we’ve succeeded in this aim, we've certainly told many sides of many stories in this book (some might wonder: did we tell too many?) – and the result is that the chapters are lengthier than is typical. There are already quite a few short introductions to epistemology on the market, and it's fair to say that this is not one of them. What we lack in brevity we hope to have overcome in comprehensiveness.
I.12 In the next section, we describe briefly what each of the 11 chapters is about. But before proceeding to do that, we want to first say at least something a bit more general about what unifies epistemology as a subject matter – something that (in some way or another) the reader might fruitfully view as a kind of “common denominator” among the 11 themes canvassed.
I.13 On this score, we take a cue from one of the world's leading epistemologists, Timothy Williamson, who embraces a simple and elegant way of dividing up the “cognitive” and the “practical” aspects of intelligent human life.10 Williamson calls “cognitive” those aspects of intelligent life which concern fitting mind to world, and “practical” those which concern fitting world to mind. His suggestion that the cognitive and the practical have different “directions of fit” (mind‐to‐world and world‐to‐mind) might seem like a confusing or perhaps superfluous way to try to put things, but bear with us.11
I.14 Think for a moment about how some of our mental states are different from others. In particular, think about the difference between a belief and a desire. A desire is realized or satisfied only when the world is adapted in some way to “fit” the desire. If you desire that it stops raining, then your desire is satisfied only if the rain actually stops, and not otherwise. In this respect, “desire” is (on Williamson's way of cutting up the cognitive and the practical) a practical mental state. It doesn't aim at merely representing things as they are (i.e. at working out whether it is in fact raining), but at having things actually become a certain way – the way that they are desired to be – and the desire is satisfied (or, more generally, “realized”) when (and only when) they become that way.
I.15 Beliefs in this respect are satisfied in the opposite kind of way. When they succeed (e.g. by being true, or known), it's because they “fit” how the world already is (regardless of how it is desired to be). The direction of fit that characterizes beliefs is accordingly a mind‐to‐world direction of fit, rather than a world‐to‐mind direction of fit (like desires, hopes, wishes, intentions, etc.) Beliefs are the kinds of things that, when they succeed, succeed because things actually are as they are believed to be, because the mind “fits” the world.
I.16 Having defined the cognitive and the practical aspects of intelligent life in this way (lumping beliefs on the side of the cognitive and desires on the side of the practical), we might now say a bit about the more general subject matter of epistemology in terms of the cognitive.
I.17 To a first approximation, the subject matter of epistemology is the cognitive rather than the practical part of intelligent life. And given that the cognitive is concerned with fitting mind to world, so is epistemology concerned with fitting mind to world, and with the various ways humans (and perhaps also animals) go about trying to do that. We can now take things a step further. Epistemology is not merely about describing the cognitive part of intelligent life (if it were, then there would be no clear difference between the aims of epistemology and cognitive science12). Rather – and this is important – it's fundamentally about evaluating the cognitive part of intelligent life.
I.18 Just as when we evaluate someone's attempt to put a puzzle together, we might evaluate how they're doing under various kinds of situations (e.g. when all the pieces are in plain view, when only some are, when some pieces are accidentally the wrong shape, etc.), we can also evaluate a person's attempt to fit mind to world under various kinds of situations – for example, when