Liberty in Mexico. Группа авторов
means to make it actual. How is it possible to proceed in this way without sanctioning or supposing the omnipotence of deliberative bodies? What limits can be placed upon the action of a body that does not recognize these limits in individual
[print edition page 53]
rights and believes itself authorized to deprive anyone of the means of maintaining them? If there are injustices in the world, without doubt this is the greatest of all.
The general will must not be a reason that justifies such ravaging; it cannot be unlimited, and its action must cease where the right of another begins. Where would we end up by asserting the principle that the general will can do everything and is sufficient by itself to legitimate doing so? The most repressive and tyrannical acts, the most barbarous proscriptions, and the most enormous crimes would need nothing to convert themselves into rights except a certain number of votes, which could not even be fixed, given that nations cannot consist of a precise and determinate number of persons. The death of Socrates and Phocian, the exile of Aristides and Miltiades, and a thousand other loathsome acts through the entire human lineage would remain fully justified by such an absurd and antisocial doctrine. In a word, the ignominious execution of Jesus of Nazareth, the most innocent, the most beneficent, the most virtuous, and to say it now, the greatest of the whole line among the children of men, would be nothing other than a lawful act and the exercise of a right essential to all society.
Nonetheless, there is no one who does not know and detest such injustices, and this is the most decisive proof that there does not exist on earth any unlimited power or authority, and even were the votes and opinions of the entire human race gathered, they would not be sufficient to justify what by itself and by its nature is necessarily unjust.
Well, now, if the gathering of all rational beings cannot bestow this character on certain acts, can some fractions of it, much less the very few called representatives, be invested with such power? It would be nonsense and the height of absurdity to maintain it.
But what rights are violated, it will be asked of us, by changing, through laws of exception in certain and determinate cases, the tribunals and forms of trials, omitting some proceedings when public safety is in danger? We do not have difficulty in asserting that many and almost all rights are violated, because either those tribunals and forms have been considered absolute and indispensably necessary to guarantee individual security and distinguish the innocent from the guilty, or not. If they are necessary, in no case can the tribunals be changed or the forms omitted without attacking the most sacred right of man, which consists of the independence
[print edition page 54]
of his person and in the free use of the indispensable means to make clear his innocence. If they are not necessary, the tribunals must not be established, nor the forms agreed to.
To clarify. When the ordinary tribunals were established they had to be constituted on such foundations that, at the same time they threatened crime they protected innocence, inspiring in this way confidence in the individuals and the government. They had to be, under one aspect, a bulwark of individual security and, under another, the maintainer of public tranquility. To attempt, then, to keep them from exercising their functions in certain cases is to expose the one or the other, and sometimes both, to being trampled and destroyed. There will be a reason, perhaps, to change their program and method of proceeding if experience proves in them some imperfections inseparable from human institutions, but it will be impossible, at any given time, to detect these imperfections in order to deny these tribunals jurisdiction over some crimes.
We say the same about judicial forms. They have been established as an essential means to make clear the innocence or guilt of an accused person. Thus it is that the achievement of this most important goal depends on their exact and faithful observance, and to abandon the goal is to be rendered absolutely and totally powerless to rule with certainty and obtain a happy outcome in so delicate a matter. There is no halfway. If the forms do not lead to making clear the truth of an accusation and the certainty of a crime, they should be dropped altogether; but if on the contrary they are considered necessary to the purpose, they must never be set aside.
Nor can the risk of threatened public security be given as an excuse sufficient to justify such provisions because, besides the fact that public security cannot be distinguished from individual security and he who attacks the interests of the first can hardly look after the second, we have already demonstrated that the tribunals and procedures in which one can have confidence in the punishment of some crimes should inspire confidence that the tribunals and procedures can curb them all.
Nothing, then, can exonerate laws of exception from the mark of injustice and the tendency to despotism; not the authority of the legislative bodies that receive that authority from the people, nor the authority of the people, because by its nature and essence that authority is necessarily limited by individual rights; nor public security, because
[print edition page 55]
public security can be provided through ordinary means; generally, public security is not at risk except when the civil liberty of the citizen is attacked, and fear of this ceases with the renunciation of extraconstitutional methods. A procedure of that kind remains, then, nothing more than an act of arbitrariness and despotism by legislative bodies, by means of which they overstep, without reason, the boundaries imposed by principles of natural justice, engraved with indelible characters in the hearts of all men. But it is not the only error from which these agreements that are incorrectly called laws suffer; illegality, disloyalty, and inconsistency are what constitute their distinctive character and make them more odious to all men in general because they grasp more clearly the contrast noted between promises set out in fundamental laws and the violations of these promises by laws of exception.
Any system in which one acts contrary to a compulsory law and through which a previously made commitment is ignored is called illegal and deceitful. These ideas are clear, precise, and widely accepted. The wise and the ignorant, the concerned and the impartial cannot help but know their truth. We come, then, to the application that can be made of them in the subject with which we are dealing.
If there is any universal and preferentially compulsory law in society, it is the fundamental code. A constitution is clearly nothing if it is not the law of all the others and if it does not obligate all the powers of a nation in the same way as those individuals who make it up. As soon as the subsidiary laws can withdraw from the rule of constitutive law, restrict it, violate it, or suspend it, it becomes reduced to a magnificent façade and an illusory monument behind which the chains of despotism are devised and forged. If the constitution is the only ineffective one among all the laws, and if it can do nothing against the other laws which can do anything against it; if it exists only to receive insults, what kind of obligation does one have to observe it, and how is one to understand that immutability that one ventures to grant it? An obligatory and immutable law is one that binds everyone and from whose observance no one is exempt. Its destruction begins from the moment any one of its literal provisions is disobeyed or thwarted, even by acts that are called legislative, and it remains without authority if, in any of its questions that have been resolved positively, any text other than it is consulted.
When legislators enter into the exercise of their august functions, they renew by a public and authentic act the commitment that, in the
[print edition page 56]
role of individuals, they contracted to observe it, and at the same time they assume another new commitment not to oppose it by acts that might destroy it. This solemn affirmation establishes a right in each one of the citizens to object not only to their nonobservance but also to their positive infraction. Those who dare to offer this proof of respect and obedience for the fundamental law, simply by confirming it, agree that they will consider null and illegal all acts that in any way might oppose it, and because among them must be counted the laws of exception, it is as clear as the light of midday that its provisions share in these judgments.
In effect, if the constitutional law of a nation is the statement of the rights that the entirety of citizens should enjoy and the exercise of these should be specified by the secondary laws, and if the first should proclaim the principles and the second ensure their being carried out, no people who obtain a fundamental code