A Companion to Chomsky. Группа авторов

A Companion to Chomsky - Группа авторов


Скачать книгу
of Chicago Press.

      79 Postal, P. 1971. Cross‐over Phenomena. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.

      80 Postal, P. 1974. On Raising: One Rule of English grammar and Its Theoretical Implications. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

      81 Potsdam, E. and M. Polinsky. 2012. “Backward Raising.” Syntax 15, 75–108. DOI: 10.1111/j.1467‐9612.2011.00158.x.

      82 Reinhart, T. 1976. The Syntactic Domain of Anaphora. PhD diss., MIT.

      83 Riemsdijk, H. van and E. Williams. 1981. “NP‐structure.” The Linguistic Review 1, 171–217. DOI: 10.1515/tlir.1981.1.2.171.

      84 Rosenbaum, P. 1967. The Grammar of English Predicate Complement Constructions. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

      85 Ross, J. R. 1967. Constraints on Variables in Syntax. PhD diss., MIT.

      86 Sag, I. A. and C. J. Pollard. 1991. “An Integrated Theory of Complement Control.” Language 67, 63–113. DOI: 10.2307/415539.

      87 Schütze, C. T. 2020. “Acceptability Ratings Cannot Be Taken at Face Value.” In Linguistic Intuitions, edited by S. Schindler, A. Drozdzowicz, and K. Brøcker 189–214. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

      88 Schütze, C. T. and J. Sprouse. 2013. “Judgment Data.” In Research Methods in Linguistics, edited by R. J. Podesva and D. Sharma, 22–50. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

      89 Speas, M. 1986. Adjunctions and Projections in Syntax. PhD diss., MIT.

      90 Sprouse, J. and D. Almeida. 2012. “Assessing the Reliability of Textbook Data in Syntax: Adger's Core Syntax.” Journal of Linguistics 48, 609–652. DOI: 10.1017/S0022226712000011.

      91 Sprouse, J. and D. Almeida 2013. “The Empirical Status of Data in Syntax: A reply to Gibson and Fedorenko.” Language and Cognitive Processes 28, 222–228. DOI: 10.1080/01690965.2012.703782.

      92 Sprouse, J. and D. Almeida. 2017a. “Design Sensitivity and Statistical Power in Acceptability Judgment Experiments.” Glossa: A Journal of General Linguistics 2 (1), e14. DOI: 10.5334/gjgl.236.

      93 Sprouse, J. and D. Almeida. 2017b. “Setting the Empirical Record Straight: Acceptability Judgments appear to be Reliable, Robust, and Replicable.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 40, e311. DOI: 10.1017/S0140525X17000590.

      94 Sprouse, J., C. T. Schütze and D. Almeida. 2013. “A Comparison of Informal and Formal Acceptability Judgments Using a Random Sample from Linguistic Inquiry 2001–2010.” Lingua 134, 219–248. DOI: 10.1016/j.lingua.2013.07.002.

      95 Travis, L. 1984. Parameters and Effects of Word Order Variation. PhD diss., MIT.

      96 Wasow, T. and J. Arnold. 2005. “Intuitions in Linguistic Argumentation.” Lingua 115, 1481–1496. DOI: 10.1016/j.lingua.2004.07.001.

      97 Webelhuth, G. 1992. Principles and Parameters of Syntactic Saturation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

      TIM HUNTER

      University of California–Los Angeles, Los Angeles, California

      Intersubstitutability is closely related to the way different levels on the Chomsky hierarchy correspond to different kinds of memory. A grammar that will give rise to the intersubstitutability of cat and dog is one that ignores, or forgets, all the ways that they differ, collapsing all distinctions between them. Similarly for larger expressions: the distinctions between wash the clothes and go to a bar, such as the fact that they differ in number of words and the fact that only one of the two contains the word the, can be ignored. The flip side of this irrelevant information, that a grammar ignores, is the relevant information that a grammar tracks – this remembered, relevant information is essentially the idea of a category. Different kinds of grammars correspond to different kinds of memory in the sense that they differ in how these categories, this remembered information, are used to guide or constrain subsequent generative steps.

      Much of the discussion below aims to show that this idea of intersubstitutability gets at the core of how any sort of grammar differs from a mere collection of sentences, and how any sort of grammar might finitely characterize an infinite collection of expressions. A mechanism that never collapsed distinctions between expressions would be forced to specify all combinatorial possibilities explicitly, leaving no room for any sort of productivity; a mechanism that collapsed all distinctions would treat all expressions as intersubstitutable and impose no restrictions on how expressions combine to form others. An “interesting” grammar is one that sits somewhere in between these two extremes, collapsing some but not all distinctions, thereby giving rise to constrained productivity – productivity stems from the distinctions that are ignored, while constraints stem from those that are tracked. The task of designing a grammar to generate some desired pattern amounts to choosing which distinctions to ignore and which distinctions to track.


Скачать книгу