Probability and Statistical Inference. Robert Bartoszynski

Probability and Statistical Inference - Robert Bartoszynski


Скачать книгу
programs, etc.) built for sampling random chords. One scheme chooses a point on the circumference, and then the angle images between the chord and the tangent to the circle at the point chosen (Figure 2.2). The second scheme chooses first the direction of the diameter and then the point images on the diameter, at which the chord perpendicular to this diameter intersects it (Figure 2.3). From Figure 2.5, it is seen that the angle images is images, and therefore images. Thus, images, which means that equal changes of images do not produce equal changes of images. In fact, these changes are smaller when images is small. Consequently, a device that chooses angles images at random will tend to produce more intersections of the diameter that are farther from the center (i.e., more chords will be shorter).

      Problems

      1 2.3.1 Label all statements below as true or false. (i) If is more likely to occur than , then . (ii) If occurs whenever does, then . (iii) If then whenever occurs, does also. (iv) If , then must occur three times out of every four. (v) The sum of probabilities of disjoint events and cannot exceed 1. (vi) If and are not disjoint, the sum of their probabilities exceeds 1. (vii) If and are all positive, then is also positive. (viii) If sample spaces for two experiments are identical, then the probability of the same event must be the same for both experiments.

      2 2.3.2 A bathroom floor is covered by square tiles with side length . You drop a coin with diameter , where . Find: (i) The probability that the coin will rest entirely within one tile. (ii) The probability that the coin will partially cover four different tiles.

      3 2.3.3 Show that first and third, as well as second and third, schemes of sampling chords (see Bertrand's paradox) are not equivalent.

      

      The simplest consequences of the axioms of probability are as follows:

      1 The probability of the impossible event is zero:(2.1) This follows from the fact which is possible only if . It is important to realize that the converse is not true: the condition does not imply that . This is shown by the following example:Example 2.4Consider an experiment consisting of tossing a coin infinitely many times. The outcomes may be represented as infinite sequences of the form HHTHTTHT …so that the sample space contains infinitely many of such sequences. The event “heads only,” that is, the set consisting of just one sequence HHHH …, is not empty. However, the chance of such an outcome is, at least intuitively, zero: tails should come up sooner or later.

      2 Probability is finitely additive:for any if the events are pairwise disjoint.In an infinite sequence events are pairwise disjoint only if are, so Axiom 3 applies. Therefore, using (2.1), we havewhile the left‐hand side is

      3 Monotonicity: If then . This follows from the fact that . The events on the right‐hand side are disjoint, so we have by Axiom 1. Since for every event , we have

      4 Probability is countably subadditive:(2.2) for every sequence of events This follows from representation (1.6) as a union of disjoint events, and then from monotonicity. We have

      5 Complementation:(2.3) This follows from Axiom 2, by the fact that and are disjoint and .

      6 Probability of a union of events:(2.4) Indeed, since , then . On the other hand, , and hence, . Solving for in one equation and substituting into the other, we obtain (2.4).

A Venn diagram depicting the union of two events A and B. Each sample point from the intersection A ∩ B is included twice, to obtain the probability of the union A ∪ B.

      Example 2.5

      Suppose that images. Find images.

      Solution

      For the case of three events: images and images, the same argument based on Venn diagrams gives the formula