Art in Theory. Группа авторов

Art in Theory - Группа авторов


Скачать книгу
issue on the basis of similarity and fragments of ancient writing, on the basis of the ancient Greek style itself, and see what these, without prejudice, tell us.

      Analogy shows that individuals and peoples extremely seldom invent when they do not have to, that they always, except in dire necessity, choose to make do with tradition, inheritance, imitation, learning from others rather than thinking things up for themselves. However little this redounds to the honour of mankind, it is so. We can see it in ourselves, in every child of every people. We invent extremely little on our own account: the most highly praised inventions are mere flashes of inspiration generated by the friction between the most carefully prepared circumstances and, as it were, prior inventions, but even here humankind discovers far more often than it invents. The chain of culture among the few peoples of the world shows how much a people can achieve through contact, tradition, looking beyond its own boundaries, and how little by itself, idle and isolated. A self‐enclosed people can remain uncultured in the least expected areas. By making do alone it will hardly, or only with difficulty, progress even in the bare necessities of life and those on plainest view, let alone in the habits and pleasures of the mind. Why has that which we call art and science taken hold in, and made an impression on, such a narrow swathe of the Earth? Clearly, climate, government and so on cannot be responsible for everything because they vary greatly across the small number of cultivated nations. Tradition, learning from others, the chain of instruction do the most – and above all, no doubt, where the mechanical aspects of art are concerned.

      ***

      I would just like to say a word about Egyptian art by way of a second test. That Winckelmann considered the art of the Egyptians not as a Greek, but within the context of his theoretical system for Greek art, is undeniable, after all beauty and the essence of art are everywhere the same, resting on a common set of rules. However, it is another matter altogether if we are to view the history of art as history pure and simple rather than as a system. The Egyptians are older than the Greeks and need to be judged not against the latter but on their own merits. What was art to the Egyptians? How, in their great antiquity, did they light upon the idea of it? And what was its purpose among them? Had they nothing in common with the Greeks in all of this, the works of the two should not be seen as part of the same framework but should each be allowed to serve its particular time and place. After all, going back to their origins, the Egyptians most likely intended working neither for the Greeks nor for us.

      I could propose another, similar test concerning the Egyptians’ depiction of animals and why their art attained such excellence in this field. The above suffices, however, to demonstrate that just like Greek art, Egyptian and Etruscan art need to be dealt with quite individually, rather than simply negatively or privatively on the basis of comparison. In all of this a fine laurel wreath awaits whoever is capable of seeing the history of art not as a system but as history, showing clearly, in every instance, on the basis of which writings and about which periods and monuments of which specific people he is speaking. And this is something we do not really find in Winckelmann. His history of art has few points of support, and indeed as a theoretical system can do no more than hang in the air.


Скачать книгу