Digital Media Ethics. Charles Ess

Digital Media Ethics - Charles  Ess


Скачать книгу
analogue and digital media are only one side of the coin. As advocates of the post-digital remind us (Cascone 2000; Berry 2014), however much our media technologies have changed in recent decades, the human eyes, ears, and voices have not: we as embodied beings still generate and receive information in resolutely analogue form. The digital codes, for example, that pass between two computers or smartphones, whether in the form of a Skype call, Facebook update, or phone call, begin and end for their human users as analogue information. The emergence of “the digital,” in short, does not mean the quick and complete end of “the analogue” (cf. Massumi 2002). This is critical to keep in mind especially from an ethical perspective: as digital media build on and enhance – rather than replace – our analogue modes of communication and experiences, they thereby call into play experiences and communication that have been part and parcel of human ethical reflection and frameworks for millennia. This is good news, ethically. That is, it is sometimes argued – and tempting to think – that the ethical experiences and challenges of digital media are so strikingly new that they require entirely new frameworks (e.g., Braidotti 2006). But these continuities with our experiences as analogue and embodied beings argue that the emergence of digital media does not require us to throw out all previous ethical reflections and views and somehow try to start de novo – from the beginning. On the contrary, we will see several examples of how older forms of ethical reflection (perhaps, most notably, virtue ethics) – however transformed through their applications within digital media – are often key in helping us analyze and successfully resolve contemporary ethical dilemmas.

      Digital media thus conjoin both traditional and sometimes new sorts of information sources. In particular, what were once distinct kinds of information in the analogue world (e.g., photographs, texts, music) now share the same basic form of information. What does this mean, finally, for ethics? Here’s the key point: what were once distinct sets of ethical issues now likewise converge – sometimes creating new combinations of ethical challenges that we haven’t had to face before.

      A second characteristic of digital media is that digital information is “greased.” That is, as James Moor (1997) has observed, “When information is computerized, it is greased to slide easily and quickly to many ports of call” (27). As anyone who has hit the “post” button on a status update too quickly knows all too well, information in digital form can spread more or less instantaneously and globally, whether we always want it to or not.

      As the example of uploading embarrassing photos or videos from a smartphone suggests, the near-instantaneous and potentially global distribution of digital information raises especially serious ethical issues surrounding privacy. Where it was once comparatively difficult to capture and then transmit information about a person that she or he might consider private, digital media, beginning with computer databases that store and make easily accessible a vast range of information about people, have resulted in an extensive spectrum of new threats to personal and private information. Moreover, digital information as “greased” likewise makes it easy to copy and distribute, say, one’s favorite songs, movies, or texts. To be sure, it has always been possible to copy and distribute copies of a given text, song, or film. But the ease of doing so with digital media is a primary factor in the central problems of copying, copyright, and so on.

      Secondly, the diffusion of internet and Web-based connectivity by way of smartphones and other digital devices (e.g., the sensor devices a jogger wears to track


Скачать книгу