Society of Singularities. Andreas Reckwitz

Society of Singularities - Andreas Reckwitz


Скачать книгу
the same type.

      The general-particular should not be confused with what I would like to call idiosyncrasies. Here one can begin again with the difference between the general and the particular and maintain that idiosyncrasies are aspects of entities that cannot be made to fit into the concepts or schemata of the general: residual, idiosyncratic characteristics. This could be a feature of a given chair that goes beyond the idea of chairs as a general type – for instance, the specific wear and tear that it has suffered in a particular household over the years, or the memory that one’s grandmother once used to sit in it. Viewed in this way, idiosyncrasies are peculiar features that not only do not fit into the general but also oppose the orders of the general-particular.

      Such a defensive understanding of idiosyncrasies, which presumes the primacy of the general, can be converted into a bold understanding. In bolder terms, one could say that all of the world’s entities exist initially as idiosyncrasies.4 They are special; they are unique to the extent that, in principle, they remain incommensurable with other entities. Nothing is identical with anything else; no entity can be converted into another without losing some quality. In this sense, every person is idiosyncratic, as is every plant, animal, or element of inorganic nature, not to mention every house or tool, every image and text, every location, every memory, every collective, and every belief. Thus understood, peculiarities are not the result of intentional design or the object of conscious appreciation or rejection; rather, as multiplicities, they are simply there – either independent of the existence of human beings (stones, animals, the cosmos, etc.) or as unintended side-effects of human activity (that is, as side-effects of the social). Regardless of whether idiosyncrasies are interpreted defensively or boldly, what is crucial is that they are unique features existing outside of the orders of the general that are not perceived as anything special by the social sphere itself. As unique features “in themselves,” they are marginal cases both for the social world and for the (social) sciences. Though ubiquitous, they are nearly invisible.

      Within a social logic of singularities, particularities cannot be reduced to a general schema; rather, they appear unique and are certified as such. Whereas the general-particular designates variations of the same and idiosyncrasy designates pre-social peculiarity, singularity denotes socio-culturally fabricated uniqueness. To begin with, it is possible to define these unique entities in negative terms: as non-generalizable, non-interchangeable, and incomparable. Singular objects, subjects, places, events, and collectives are not merely exemplars of a general order. Stanley Kubrick’s film A Clockwork Orange may admittedly belong to the genre of science fiction, but – in the complexity of its imagery and narration and in its unique tension between fascination and disgust – it cannot be reduced to this or any other type. Cineastes view and experience it as unique. Moreover, a singularity cannot be exchanged for or replaced by a different but functionally identical entity, as readily happens to functional objects and people within the framework of the logic of the general. For those who participated in it, the subculture of mods during the 1960s could not simply be exchanged for another subculture – the rockers, say – but rather developed a subcultural universe of its own with specific practices, symbols, affects, and identities. Finally, a singularity cannot be compared to other entities with any clear parameters, because no overarching standard exists along which it might be possible to measure their differences. To believers, for instance, it would make no sense to compare Shinto’s Ise Grand Shrine to the Church of the Holy Sepulcher in Jerusalem.

      Complexity and density are characteristics of the internal structure of singularities, and this is why I have used the terms inherent complexity and inner density. Singular entities, however, also have a specific relation to the outside. Yet it would be insufficient to claim that there are simply certain differences between them (between the urban logic of Rome and San Francisco, for instance). Of course, difference theory has taught us that, in the socio-cultural realm, it would be impossible to identify any entities at all without the existence of differences, because every entity is constituted in the first place by being different from others.7 Despite its general appeal to cultural theorists, however, it would be a mistake to embrace difference theory fully, for it would bring two serious disadvantages to the analysis of singularities. First, the social relevance of the inherent complexity of entities would be marginalized in favor of the ostensibly ubiquitous “play of differences.” Second, it would raise the risk of losing the capacity to distinguish between the multiplicities of differences that exist in the social world.

      It must be stressed that, in the social logic of singularities, differences are certainly identified, but the main issue involves the production and appropriation of inherent complexities. What this means can best be illustrated with an example, for instance American literature. In this case, there are countless ways to identify a difference between the novels of Edith Wharton, John Dos


Скачать книгу