Philosophy of Psychology. Lisa Bortolotti

Philosophy of Psychology - Lisa Bortolotti


Скачать книгу
with evidence instead of merely stamping their foot in a debate (Bortolotti 2014). But rationality as logicality, as we might call it, is widely accepted in philosophy, economics, and psychology. For instance, Phil Gerrans says that ‘a rational subject is one whose reasoning conforms to procedures, such as logical rules, or Bayesian decision theory, which produce inferentially consistent sets of propositions’ (Gerrans 2001, 161), and Richard Nisbett and Paul Thagard define rational behaviour as ‘what people should do given an optimal set of inferential rules’ (Thagard & Nisbett 1983, 251).

      There are some technical issues about the standard picture of rationality that we would like to mention briefly here.

      First, the standard picture seems to presuppose that there is just one system of logic, one theory of probability, and one set of principles for decision-making. However, there are different formal systems of logic and different interpretations of probability; even the principles of decision-making can be disputed. Some rules of inference that are valid in standard logic (often called classical logic) are not valid in some non-classical logical systems. This raises a question: which system of logic should be adopted in evaluating the reasoning performance of agents? This is especially tricky if reasoning performance is consistent with one system of logic but not with another. Should we adopt the former and say that an agent’s performance is rational? Or should we adopt the latter and say that it is irrational? A similar issue arises when considering interpretations of probability. There are different interpretations of what probabilistic statements (e.g., there is a 80% chance that it will rain tomorrow) actually mean. There are also some probabilistic statements that make sense in some interpretations but not in others. This issue is relevant to the debate between pessimists and optimists. Gigerenzer, the most notable optimist, argues that some probabilistic questions in the heuristics and biases experiments are meaningless in light of his favourite interpretation of probability (which is known as the frequency interpretation). This issue will be discussed in Section 1.5.

      Second, the standard picture assumes that our reasoning should be evaluated against the standards of logic, probability, and decision-making. This implies that, if our intuitive answer to a reasoning task is incompatible with a rule of logic, we should conclude that our intuition is at fault. But why can’t we say that it is logic, not intuition, that is at fault? In fact, the development of non-classical logic is sometimes at least partially motivated by some counter-intuitive features of classic logic.

      Here is a tentative answer to the philosophical question (with the qualifications we made at the end of the previous section): ‘rationality’ consists in reasoning in accordance with the rules of logic, probability, and decision-making.

      According to deductive logic, for a conditional statement of the form ‘If P then Q’ to be falsified, the antecedent (P) must be true and the consequent (Q) must be false. So, the statement ‘If you want to go to Brighton, then you need to catch the next train’ is false if you do want to go to Brighton but you don’t need to catch the next train.


Скачать книгу