Philosophy of Psychology. Lisa Bortolotti

Philosophy of Psychology - Lisa Bortolotti


Скачать книгу
well as empirical inputs.

      Suppose that you are interested in whether humans have some property X, such as the property of being rational or the property of being altruistic. To answer this, you need to investigate two sets of questions: (1) ‘What does it mean to have X?’, ‘What is necessary for a person to have X?’, and ‘What is sufficient for a person to have X?’; and (2) ‘Do humans satisfy a sufficient condition for having X?’, ‘Do humans fail to satisfy a necessary condition for having X?’, and ‘What do empirical studies say about these issues?’ Let us call the former the ‘philosophical questions’ about X, and the latter the ‘psychological questions’ about X.

      The reason you can’t just let philosophers do what they do is that although a purely philosophical investigation is useful for addressing the philosophical questions, it does not say much about the psychological questions. For instance, a philosophical argument does not say anything about whether as a matter of fact humans can be motivated to increase somebody else’s well-being for its own sake. In contrast, the reason you can’t just let psychologists do what they do is that although a purely psychological investigation is useful for addressing the psychological questions, it does not say much about the philosophical questions. For example, a psychological experiment does not say anything about whether ‘rationality’ should be regarded as the capacity for reasoning in accordance with the rules of logic and mathematics.

      Let us think about a further example (which we discuss in detail in Chapter 6). Suppose that you want to know whether humans have free will and responsibility, according to relevant psychological findings. To know this, you need to investigate both the philosophical and the psychological questions: (1) ‘What does it mean to have free will?’, ‘What is necessary for a person to have free will?’, ‘What is sufficient for a person to have free will?’; (2) ‘Do humans satisfy a sufficient condition for having free will?’, ‘Or, do humans fail to satisfy a necessary condition for having free will?’, ‘What do empirical studies say about these issues?’

      A purely psychological investigation can address the psychological questions, but not the philosophical questions. For example, psychological studies might suggest that Elsa’s discriminatory behaviour is generated by her implicit biases, which can only be detected by psychological tests. Elsa is not introspectively aware of her biases. This is certainly an interesting finding, but we need to know more to judge whether she is responsible for her discriminatory behaviour. In particular, the philosophical questions have not yet been addressed. It is still unclear whether Elsa’s lack of introspective awareness of her implicit biases is incompatible with her being responsible for her discriminatory behaviour. As we shall see in Chapter 6, this is the topic of a recent discussion about whether people are responsible for their implicit biases.

      This book focuses on implicational philosophy of psychology, investigating the implications of some particular psychological studies. Before getting into our main discussions, we would like to mention three factors that are relevant in the context of evaluating psychological studies and their implications: replication, research participants, and ecological validity.

      Psychological studies, just like other scientific studies, need to be replicated in order to be credible. It is possible that some interesting results fail to be replicated. In fact, psychology, social psychology in particular, is now facing the so-called ‘replication crisis’ (e.g., Earp & Trafimow 2015): the replicability of social psychological studies, including some famous ones, seems to be remarkably low.

      The problem is compounded by the fact that replication failure tends not to be reported in journals (unless, just like in the case of priming studies by Bargh and colleagues, a serious controversy arises). Paul Bloom says that when the project of replicating a study turns out to be unsuccessful, ‘[u]sually, the project is just abandoned, though sometimes the word gets out in an informal way – in seminars, lab meetings, conferences – that some findings are vaporware (“Oh, nobody can replicate that one”)’ and ‘[m]any psychologists now have an attitude that if a finding seems really implausible, just wait a while and it will go away’ (Bloom 2017, 224).

      We do not necessarily endorse radical pessimism about social psychology; after all, many important studies have been replicated. But, as a general rule, replication should always be kept in mind when evaluating psychological studies, and perhaps some extra care is needed when evaluating studies in social psychology with surprising results.

      Replication really matters, but what about the observations of rare conditions about which we cannot expect statistical analysis of data or replication? Despite the lack of statistical analysis or replication, the study of some unusual behaviours can be informative and can help us to understand how the mind works. In the book Phantoms in the Brain, V. S. Ramachandran defends the usefulness of observing rare cases as opposed to the statistical study of normal individuals:


Скачать книгу